LITERATUUR



Bewustzijnsfilosofie.



A


@

Abbott, B.

(1995): Natural language and thought: Thinking in English. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.49-55.
@

Abbott, B.

(2000): Fodor and Lepore on meaning similarity and compositionality. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 97, pp.454-6.
@

Abelson, R.

(1970): A refutation of mind-body identity. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 18, pp.85-90.
@

Ackermann, D. F.

(1983): Wittgenstein, rules and origin--privacy. In: ' Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research', vol. 1, pp.63-69.
@

Adam, A.

(2003): Cyborgs in the Chinese room: Boundaries transgressed and boundaries blurred . In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): ' Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Adams, F.

(1979): Properties, functionalism, and the identity theory. In: ' Eidos', vol. 1, pp.153-79.
@

Adams, F.

(1991): Causal contents. In: B. McLaughlin (Ed.): ' Dretske and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Adams, F.

(1993): Fodor's modal argument. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 6, pp.41-56.
@

Adams, F.

(2001): Empathy, neural imaging and the theory versus simulation debate. In: 'Mind & Language', vol. 16, pp.368-392.
@

Adams, F.

(2002): Mental representation. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Adams, F.

(2003): The informational turn in philosophy. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 13, pp.471-501.
@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1992): `X' means X: Semantics Fodor-style. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 2, pp.175-83.
@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1993): Fodorian semantics, pathologies, and "Block's problem" . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 3, pp.97-104.
@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1994): `X' means X: Fodor/Warfield semantics. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.215-31.
@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1997): Fodor's asymmetric causal dependency theory and proximal projections. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 35, pp.433-437.
@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(1997): Rock beats scissors: Historicalism fights back. In: 'Analysis', vol. 57, pp.273-81.
@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.

(2001): The bounds of cognition. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.43-64.
@

Adams, F.; Aizawa, K.; Fuller, G.

(1992): Rules in programming languages and networks . In: J. Dinsmore (Ed.): 'The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Adams, F.; Drebushenko, D.; Fuller, G.; Stecker, R.

(1990): Narrow content: Fodor's folly . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 5, pp.213-29.
@

Adams, F.; Fuller, G.

(1992): Names, contents, and causes. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 7, pp.205-21.
@

Adams, W.

(2004): Machine consciousness: Plausible idea or semantic distortion?. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 11, no.9, pp.46-56.
@

Addis, L.

(1995): The ontology of emotion. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 33, pp.261-78.
@

Addis, L.

(2000): The simplicity of content. In: 'Metaphysica ', vol. 1, no.2, pp.23-44.
@

Adler, J.

(2002): Belief's Own Ethics. MIT Press.
@

Adolphs, R.

(2004): 'Edison' & 'Russell': Definitions versus inventions in the analysis of emotion. In: J. Fellous (Ed.): 'Who Needs Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Adshead, G.

(1999): Psychopaths and other-regarding beliefs. In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 99, pp.41-44.
@

Agar, N.

(1993): What do frogs really believe?. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 71, pp.1-12.
@

Agar, N.

(2003): Functionalism and personal identity. In: 'Nous ', vol. 37, pp.52-70.
@

Agre, P.

(1995): Computation and embodied agency. In: 'Informatica ', vol. 19, pp.527-35.
@

Agre, P.

(2002): The practical logic of computer work. In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): ' Computationalism: New Directions'. MIT Press.
@

Aizawa, K.

(1994): Lloyd's dialectical theory of representation. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.1-24.
@

Aizawa, K.

(1994): Representations without rules, connectionism, and the syntactic argument . In: 'Synthese', vol. 101, pp.465-92.
@

Aizawa, K.

(1997): Explaining systematicity. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp.115-36.
@

Aizawa, K.

(1997): The role of the systematicity argument in classicism and connectionism . In: S. O'Nuallain (Ed.): 'Two Sciences of Mind'. John Benjamins.
@

Aizawa, K.

(1997): Exhibiting verses explaining systematicity: A reply to Hadley and Hayward . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 7, pp.39-55.
@

Aizawa, K.

(2002): Cognitive architecture. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Alanen, L.

(2003): What are emotions about?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 67, pp.311-354.
@

Albritton, R.

(1985): Freedom of the will and freedom of action. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 59, pp.239-51.
@

Aldridge, V. C.

(1987): Kripke on Wittgenstein on Regulation. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 62, pp.375-384.
@

Aleksander, I.

(2003): Neural depictions of "world" and "self": Bringing computational understanding into the Chinese room. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Aleksander, I.; Dunmall, B.

(2003): Axioms and tests for the presence of minimal consciousness in agents I: Preamble. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 10.
@

Alexander, P.

(1959): Other people's experiences. In: '1959'.
@

Alexander, S.

(1920): Space, Time, and Deity. Macmillan.
@

Allen, A. H. B.

(1952): Other minds. In: 'Mind', vol. 61, pp.328-348.
@

Allen, B.

(1989): Gruesome arithmetic: Kripke's sceptic replies. In: ' Dialogue', vol. 28, pp.257-264.
@

Allen, C.

(1992): Mental content. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 43, pp.537-53.
@

Allen, C.

(1995): It isn't what you think: A new idea about intentional causation. In: 'Nous', vol. 29, pp.115-26.
@

Allen, C.

(1997): Animal cognition and animal minds. In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind'. Pittsburgh University Press.
@

Allen, C.

(1999): Animal concepts revisited: the use of self-monitoring as an empirical approach. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp.537-544.
@

Allen, C.

(2004): Is anyone a cognitive ethologist?. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.589-607.
@

Allen, C.; Bekoff, M.

(1992): On aims and methods of cognitive ethology. In: 'Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 1992.
@

Allen, C.; Bekoff, M.

(1995): Cognitive ethology and the intentionality of animal behavior . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 10, pp.313-328.
@

Allen, C.; Bekoff, M.

(1997): Species of Mind: The Philosophy and Biology of Cognitive Ethology. MIT Press.
@

Allen, C.; Hauser, M.

(1991): Concept attribution in nonhuman animals: Theoretical and methodological problems in ascribing complex mental processes . In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 58, pp.221-40.
@

Almeida, M.; Bernstein, M.

(2003): Lucky libertarianism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 22, pp.93-119.
@

Almog, J.

(2001): What Am I?: Descartes and the Mind-Body Problem. Oxford University Press.
@

Alper, G.

(1990): A psychoanalyst takes the Turing test. In: ' Psychoanalytic Review', vol. 77, pp.59-68.
@

Alston, W. P.

(1971): Varieties of priveleged access. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 8, pp.223-41.
@

Alston, W. P.

(1983): What's wrong with immediate knowledge?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 55, pp.73-96.
@

Alter, T.; Rachels, S.

(2002): Epistemicism and the combined spectrum. In: ' Ratio', vol. 17, pp.241-55.
@

Ameriks, K.

(1973): Plantinga and other minds. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 16, pp.285-91.
@

Anderson, D.

(1987): Is the Chinese room the real thing?. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 62, pp.389-93.
@

Anderson, J. R.

(1978): Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. In: 'Psychological Review', vol. 85.
@

Andler, D.

(1995): Can we knock off the shackles of syntax?. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Content'. Ridgeview.
@

Andrews, K.

(2002): Knowing mental states: The asymmetry of psychological prediction and explanation. In: Q. Smith; A. Jokic (Ed.): 'Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives'. Oxford University Press.
@

Angel, L.

(1989): How to Build a Conscious Machine. Westview Press.
@

Angel, L.

(1994): Am I a computer?. In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): ' Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons'. Academic Press.
@

Anscombe, G. E. M.

(1971): Causality and Determinism. Cambridge University Press.
@

Anscombe, G. E. M.

(1976): `Soft' determinism. In: G. Ryle (Ed.): ' Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy'. Oriel Press.
@

Anscombe, G. E. M.

(1985): Review of Saul Kripke's Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. In: 'Ethics ', vol. 95, pp.342-352.
@

Anscombe, G. E. M.

(1985): Critical Notice: Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language . In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 15, pp.103-9.
@

Antony, L.

(1989): Semantic anorexia: On the notion of content in cognitive science. In: G. Boolos (Ed.): 'Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Antony, L.

(1989): Anomalous monism and the problem of explanatory force. In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 98, pp.153-87.
@

Antony, L.

(1991): The causal relevance of the mental. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 6, pp.295-327.
@

Antony, L.

(1995): Law and order in psychology. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.429-46.
@

Antony, L.

(1997): Feeling fine about the mind. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 57, pp.381-87.
@

Antony, L.

(1999): Making room for the mental. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 95, pp.37-44.
@

Antony, L.

(2001): Brain states with attitude. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): ' Explaining Beliefs'. CSLI.
@

Antony, L.

(2001): Empty heads?. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 16, pp.193-214.
@

Antony, L. M.

(1999): Multiple realizability, projectibility, and the reality of mental properties. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 26, pp.1-24.
@

Antony, L. M.

(2003): Who's afraid of disjunctive properties?. In: ' Philosophical Issues', vol. 13, pp.1-21.
@

Antony, L. M.; Levine, J.

(1997): Reduction with autonomy. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 11, pp.83-105.
@

Antony, L.; Levine, J.

(1991): The nomic and the robust. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Antony, M. V.

(1991): Fodor and Pylyshyn on connectionism. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.321-41.
@

Antony, M. V.

(1993): Social relations and the individuation of thought. In: 'Mind', vol. 102, pp.247-61.
@

Antony, M. V.

(2003): Davidson's argument for monism. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 135, pp.1-12.
@

Appelbaum, I.

(1998): Fodor, modularity, and speech perception. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 11, pp.317-330.
@

Apter, A.

(1991): The problem of who: Multiple personality, personal identity, and the double brain. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.219-48.
@

Arbib, M.

(1989): Modularity, schemas and neurons: A critique of Fodor. In: P. Slezak (Ed.): 'Computers, Brains and Minds'. Kluwer.
@

Arbib, M.

(2004): Beware the passionate robot. In: J. Fellous (Ed.): ' Who Needs Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Arcaya, J. M.

(1989): Memory and temporality: A phenomenological alternative. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 2, pp.101-110.
@

Ariew, A.

(1996): Innateness and canalization. In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement', vol. 63, pp.19-27.
@

Ariew, A.

(2002): Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology. Oxford University Press.
@

Ariew, A.

(2003): Natural selection doesn't work that way: Jerry Fodor vs. evolutionary psychology on gradualism and saltationism. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 18, pp.478-483.
@

Arjo, D.

(1996): Sticking up for Oedipus: Fodor on intentional generalizations and broad content. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp.231-45.
@

Arkway, A.

(2000): The simulation theory, the theory theory and folk psychological explanation. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 98, pp.115-137.
@

Arlo Costa, H.; Collins, J.; Levi, I.

(1995): Desire-as-belief implies opinionation or indifference. In: 'Analysis', vol. 55, pp.2-5.
@

Armstrong, B.

(1984): Wittgenstein on private languages: It takes two to talk. In: 'Philosophical Investigations', vol. 7.
@

Armstrong, D.

(1999): The Mind-Body Problem: An Opinionated Introduction. Westview Press.
@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1968): A Materialist Theory of the Mind. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1968): The headless woman and the defense of materialism. In: 'Analysis', vol. 29, pp.48-49.
@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1969): Colour realism and the argument from microscopes. In: R. Brown; C. Rollins (Ed.): 'Contemporary Philosophy in Australia'. Humanities Press.
@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1970): The nature of mind. In: C. Borst (Ed.): ' The Mind/Brain Identity Theory'. Macmillan.
@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1973): Epistemological foundations for a materialist theory of mind . In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 40, pp.178-93.
@

Armstrong, D. M.

(1982): Metaphysics and supervenience. In: 'Critica ', vol. 42, pp.3-17.
@

Armstrong, D. M.; Malcolm, N.

(1984): Consciousness and Causality: A Debate on the Nature of Mind. Blackwell.
@

Arregui, J. V.

(1996): On the intentionality of moods: Phenomenology and linguistic analysis . In: 'American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 70, pp.397-411.
@

Arrington, R.

(1999): Machines, consciousness, and thought. In: ' Idealistic Studies', vol. 29, pp.231-243.
@

Arstila, V.

(2003): True colors, false theories. In: ' Australian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 81, pp.41-61.
@

Atherton, M.; Schwarz, R.

(1974): Linguistic innateness and its evidence. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 71.
@

Atkin A.

(1992): On consciousness: What is the role of emergence?. In: ' Medical Hypotheses', vol. 38, pp.311-14.
@

Atkinson, A. P.; Wheeler, M.

(2003): Evolutionary psychology's grain problem and the cognitive neuroscience of reasoning. In: D. Over (Ed.): ' Evolution and the Psychology of Thinking: The Debate'. Psychology Press.
@

Atkinson, A. P.; Wheeler, M.

(2004): The grain of domains: The evolutionary-psychological case against domain-general cognition. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.147-76.
@

Atkinson, A.; Wheeler, M.

(2004): The grain of domains: The evolutionary-psychological case against domain-general cognition. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.147-176.
@

Atran, S.

(2005): Adaptationism for human cognition: Strong, spurious, or weak?. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 20, pp.39-67.
@

Audi, R.

(1974): Moral responsibility, freedom, and compulsion. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 11, pp.1-14.
@

Audi, R.

(1978): The ontological status of mental images. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 21, pp.348-61.
@

Audi, R.

(1993): Mental causation: Sustaining and dynamic. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Audi, R.

(1994): Dispositional beliefs and dispositions to believe. In: ' Nous', vol. 28, pp.419-34.
@

Aune, B.

(1961): The problem of other minds. In: '1961'.
@

Aune, B.

(1966): Feigl on the mind-body problem. In: P. Feyerabend; G. Maxwell (Ed.): ' Mind, Matter, and Method: Essays in Philosophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl'. University of Minnesota Press.
@

Aune, B.

(1970): Free will, 'can', and ethics: A reply to Lehrer. In: ' Analysis', vol. 30, pp.77-83.
@

Aune, B.

(1986): Other minds after twenty years. In: '1986'.
@

Aune, B.

(1994): Speaking of selves. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 44, pp.279-93.
@

Austin, J.

(1946): Other minds. In: 'Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 20, pp.148-87.
@

Austin, J. W.

(1975): Rorty's materialism. In: 'Auslegung ', vol. 3, pp.20-28.
@

Averill, E. W.

(1985): Color and the anthropocentric problem. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 82, pp.281-303.
@

Averill, E. W.

(1992): The relational nature of color. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 101, pp.551-88.
@

Averill, E. W.; Keating, B.

(1981): Does interactionism violate a law of classical physics? . In: 'Mind', vol. 90, pp.102-7.
@

Avison, M. J.

(2002): Functional brain mapping: What is it good for? Absolutely nothing . In: 'Brain and Mind', vol. 3, pp.367-73.
@

Avramides, A.

(2001): Other Minds. Routledge.
@

Aydede, M.

(1997): Has Fodor really changed his mind on narrow content?. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.422-58.
@

Aydede, M.

(1997): Language of thought: The connectionist contribution. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 7, pp.57-101.
@

Aydede, M.

(2000): On the type/token relation of mental representations. In: 'Facta Philosophica', vol. 2, pp.23-50.
@

Aydede, M.

(2000): An analysis of pleasure vis-a-vis pain. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 61, pp.537-570.
@

Aydede, M.

(2001): Naturalism, introspection, and direct realism about pain. In: 'Consciousness and Emotion', vol. 2, pp.29-73.
@

Aydede, M.

(2005): Pain: New Essays on its Nature and the Methodology of its Study. MIT Press.
@

Aydede, M.

(2005): A critical and quasi-historical essay on theories of pain. In: M. Aydede (Ed.): 'Pain: New Essays on its Nature and the Methodology of its Study'. MIT Press.
@

Aydede, M.; Guzeldere, G.

(2002): Some foundational problems in the scientific study of pain . In: 'Philosophy of Science Supplement', vol. 69, pp.265-83.
@

Aydede, M.; Robbins, P.

(2001): Are Frege cases exceptions to intentional generalizations? . In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 31, pp.1-22.
@

Ayer, A.

(1960): Professor Malcolm on dreams. In: '1960'.
@

Ayer, A. J.

(1953): One's knowledge of other minds. In: '1953'.
@

Ayer, A. J.

(1954): Can there be a private language?. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 27.
@

Ayer, A. J.

(1954): Freedom and necessity. In: 'Philosophical Essays'.
@

Ayer, A. J.

(1956): The Problem of Knowledge. Harmondsworth.
@

Ayer, A. J.

(1980): Free will and rationality. In: Z. van Straaten (Ed.): ' Philosophical Subjects'. Oxford University Press.
@

Ayers, M.

(1968): The Refutation of Determinism. Methuen.

B


@

Bacon, J.

(1986): Supervenience, necessary coextensions, and reducibility. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 49, pp.163-76.
@

Bacon, J.

(1995): Weak supervenience supervenes. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Badcock, C.

(2004): Emotion verses reason as a genetic conflict. In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): 'Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality'. Oxford University Press.
@

Baier, A.

(1976): Mixing memory and desire. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 13, pp.213-20.
@

Baier, A.

(1990): What emotions are about. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 4, pp.1-29.
@

Baier, A.

(2004): Feelings that matter. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Baier, K.

(1962): Smart on sensations. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 40, pp.57-68.
@

Bailey, A.

(1998): Supervenience and physicalism. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 117, pp.53-73.
@

Baillie, J.

(1991): Split brains and single minds. In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 16, pp.11-18.
@

Baillie, J.

(1993): Recent work on personal identity. In: ' Philosophical Books', vol. 34, pp.193-206.
@

Baillie, J.

(1993): What matters in survival. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 31, pp.255-61.
@

Baillie, J.

(1996): Identity, relation R, and what matters: A challenge to Derek Parfit . In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 77, pp.263-267.
@

Baillie, J.

(1997): Personal identity and mental content. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 10, pp.323-33.
@

Bain, D.

(2003): Intentionalism and pain. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 53, pp.502-523.
@

Baker, G. P.; Hacker, P. M. S.

(1984): Scepticism, Rules and Language. Blackwell.
@

Baker, G. P.; Hacker, P. M. S.

(1985): Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity.
@

Baker, G.; Hacker, P.

(1984): Critical study: On misunderstanding Wittgenstein: Kripke's private language argument. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 58.
@

Baker, G.; Hacker, P.

(1986): Reply to Mr. Mounce. In: ' Philosophical Investigations', vol. 9, pp.199-204.
@

Baker, G.; and Hacker, P.

(1990): Malcolm on language and rules. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 65, pp.167-179.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1985): A farewell to functionalism. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 48, pp.1-14.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1985): Just what do we have in mind?. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 10, pp.25-48.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1986): Content by courtesy. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 84, pp.197-213.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1987): Instrumentalism: Back from the brink?. In: ' Saving Belief'.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1987): The threat of cognitive suicide. In: 'Saving Belief '.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1987): Saving Belief. Princeton University Press.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1987): Saving Belief. Princeton University Press.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1988): Cognitive suicide. In: R. Grimm; D. Merrill (Ed.): ' Contents of Thought'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1989): Instrumental intentionality. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 56, pp.303-16.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1989): Recent work in the philosophy of mind. In: ' Philosophical Books', vol. 30, pp.1-9.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1990): On a causal theory of content. In: '1990'.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1991): Has content been naturalized?. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1991): Dretske on the explanatory role of belief. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 63, pp.99-111.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1993): What beliefs are not. In: S. Wagner; R. Warner (Ed.): ' Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal'. University of Notre Dame Press.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1993): Metaphysics and mental causation. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1994): Attitudes as nonentities. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 76, pp.175-203.
@

Baker, L. R.

(1994): Content and context. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 8, pp.17-32.
@

Baker, L. R.

(2000): Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View. Cambridge University Press.
@

Baker, L. R.

(2001): Are beliefs brain states?. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): ' Explaining Beliefs'. CSLI.
@

Baker, L. R.

(2001): Practical realism defended: Replies to critics. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Explaining Beliefs'. CSLI.
@

Balaguer, M.

(1998): Attitudes without propositions. In: ' Philosophy and phenomenological research', vol. 58, pp.805-26.
@

Balaguer, M.

(1999): Libertarianism as a scientifically respectable view. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 93, pp.189-211.
@

Balaguer, M.

(2002): A coherent, naturalistic, and plausible formulation of libertarian free will. In: 'Nous ', vol. 38, pp.379-406.
@

Baldwin, M.

(1998): Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology. Westview.
@

Ballard, D.

(1991): Animate vision. In: 'Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 48, pp.57-86.
@

Bar-On, D.

(1992): On the possibility of a solitary language. In: 'Nous ', vol. 26, pp.27-46.
@

Bar-On, D.

(2000): Speaking my mind. In: 'Philsophical topics ', vol. 28, pp.1-34.
@

Bar-On, D.

(2004): Externalism and self-knowledge: Content, use, and expression. In: 'Nous', vol. 38, pp.430-55.
@

Bar-On, D.

(2004): Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge. Oxford University Press.
@

Bar-On, D.; Long, D.

(2001): Avowals and first-person privilege. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 52, pp.311-35.
@

Bar-On, D.; Long, D.

(2003): Expressing truths and knowing truths. In: B. Gertler (Ed.): 'Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge'. Ashgate.
@

Barber, A.

(1998): The pleonasticity of talk about concepts. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 89, pp.53-86.
@

Barkin, E.

(2003): Relative phenomenalism: Toward a more plausible theory of mind. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 10, no.8, pp.3-13.
@

Barkow, J.; Cosmides, L.; Tooby, J.

(1992): The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. Oxford University Press.
@

Barnes, E.

(1991): The causal history of computational activity: Maudlin and Olympia . In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 88, pp.304-16.
@

Baron-Cohen, S.; Tager-Flusberg, H.; Cohen, D. J.

(1994): Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism. Oxford University Press.
@

Barresi, J.

(1987): Prospects for the Cyberiad: Certain limits on human self-knowledge in the cybernetic age. In: ' Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior', vol. 17, pp.19-46.
@

Barresi, J.

(1999): On becoming a person. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 12, pp.79-98.
@

Barrett, H. C.

(2005): Enzymatic computation and cognitive modularity. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 20, pp.259-87.
@

Barrett, J.

(1994): Rationalizing explanation and causally relevant mental properties . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 74, pp.77-102.
@

Barrett, J.

(1995): Causal relevance and nonreductive physicalism. In: ' Erkenntnis', vol. 42, pp.339-62.
@

Barrett, J.

(1997): Individualism and the cross-contexts test. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 78, pp.242-60.
@

Barwise, J.

(1986): Information and circumstance. In: '1986'.
@

Barwise, J.

(1987): Unburdening the language of thought. In: '1987'.
@

Barwise, J.; Perry, J.

(1983): Situations and Attitudes. MIT Press.
@

Bateson, P. P. G.; Klopfer, P. H.

(1991): Perspectives in Ethology, Volume 9: Human Understanding and Animal Awareness. Plenum Press.
@

Batitsky, V.

(1998): A formal rebuttal of the central argument for fnuctionalism. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 49, pp.201-20.
@

Bayne, T.; Pacherie, E.

(2004): Bottom-up or top-down: Campbell's rationalist account of monothematic delusions. In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology,', vol. 11.
@

Bayne, T.; Pacherie, E.

(2005): In defence of the doxastic conception of delusions. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 20, pp.163-88.
@

Bealer, G.

(1978): An inconsistency in functionalism. In: '1978'.
@

Bealer, G.

(1985): Mind and anti-mind: Why thinking has no functional definition. In: 'Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 9, pp.283-328.
@

Bealer, G.

(1986): The logical status of mind. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 10.
@

Bealer, G.

(1987): The boundary between philosophy and cognitive science. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 86, pp.553-55.
@

Bealer, G.

(1997): Self-consciousness. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 106, pp.69-117.
@

Bealer, G.

(2001): The self-consciousness argument: Why Tooley's criticisms fail. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 105, pp.281-307.
@

Beardman, S.

(2000): The choice between current and retrospective evaluations of pain. 13:97-110. :dez, J. L. 2001: Normativity and rationality in delusional psychiatric disorders . In: 'Mind & Language,', vol. 16.
@

Beauregard, M.

(2004): Consciousness, Emotional Self-Regulation and the Brain. John Benjamins.
@

Beavers, A. F.

(2002): Phenomenology and artificial intelligence. In: ' Metaphilosophy', vol. 33, pp.70-82.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1983): A bridge between cognitive science and neuroscience: The functional architecture of mind. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 44, pp.319-30.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1984): Autonomous psychology: What it should and should not entail. In: 'Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 1984.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1985): Realism, instrumentalism, and the intentional stance. In: 'Cognitive Science', vol. 9, pp.265-92.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1985): Are the new PDP models of cognition cognitivist or associationist? . In: 'Behaviorism', vol. 13, pp.53-61.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1986): What happens to accounts of mind-brain relations if we forgo an architecture of rules and representations?. In: 'Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 1986.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1987): Connectionism and the philosophy of mind. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 26, pp.17-41.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1988): Connectionism and rules and representation systems: Are they compatible? . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 1, pp.5-16.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1988): Philosophy of Mind: An Overview for Cognitive Science. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1993): The case for connectionism. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 71, pp.119-54.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1994): Levels of description and explanation in cognitive science. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.1-25.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1996): Yet another revolution: Defusing the dynamical system theorists' attack on mental representations.
@

Bechtel, W.

(1996): Yet another revolution? Defusing the dynamical system theorists' attack on mental representations.
@

Bechtel, W.

(2001): Cognitive neuroscienec: Relating neural mechanisms and cognition . In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences'. University of Pittsburgh Press.
@

Bechtel, W.

(2001): Decomposing and localizing vision: An exemplar for cognitive neuroscience. In: W. Bechtel; P. Mandik; J. Mundale; and R. Stufflebeam (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader'. Blackwell.
@

Bechtel, W.

(2002): Decomposing the mind-brain: A long-term pursuit. In: ' Brain and Mind', vol. 3, pp.229-42.
@

Bechtel, W.

(2002): Aligning multiple research techniques in cognitive neuroscience: Why is it important?. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 69, pp.548-558.
@

Bechtel, W.; Abrahamsen, A. A.

(1992): Connectionism and the future of folk psychology . In: R. Burton (Ed.): 'Minds: Natural and Artificial'. SUNY Press.
@

Bechtel, W.; Abrahamson, A.

(1990): Beyond the exclusively propositional era. In: 'Synthese', vol. 82, pp.223-53.
@

Bechtel, W.; Mandik, P.; Mundale, J.; and Stufflebeam, R. S.

(2001): Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader. Blackwell.
@

Bechtel, W.; Mundale, J.

(1999): Multiple realizability revisited: Linking cognitive and neural states. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 66, pp.175-207.
@

Bechtel, W.; Stufflebeam, R.

(2001): Epistemic issues in procuring evidence about the brain: The importance of research instruments and techniques. In: W. Bechtel; P. Mandik; J. Mundale; and R. Stufflebeam (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader'. Blackwell.
@

Beck, S.

(1989): Parfit and the Russians (personal identity and moral concepts). In: 'Analysis', vol. 49, pp.205-209.
@

Beck, S.

(2001): Let's exist again (like we did last Summer). In: ' South African Journal of Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.159-170.
@

Becker, K.

(1998): On the perfectly general nature of instability in meaning holism. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 95, pp.635-640.
@

Beckerman, A.

(2001): The real reason for the standard view. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Explaining Beliefs'. CSLI.
@

Beckermann, A, Flohr, H.; Kim, J.

(1992): Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism. De Gruyter.
@

Beckermann, A, Flohr, H.; Kim, J.

(1992): Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism. De Gruyter.
@

Beckermann, A.

(1992): Reductive and nonreductive physicalism. In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism'. De Gruyter.
@

Beckermann, A.

(1992): Supervenience, emergence, and reduction. In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism'. De Gruyter.
@

Beckermann, A.

(1996): Is there a problem about intentionality?. In: ' Erkenntnis', vol. 45, pp.1-24.
@

Beckermann, A.

(1997): Property physicalism, reduction, and realization. In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind'. Pittsburgh University Press.
@

Beckermann, A.

(2001): Physicalism and new wave reductionism. In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 61, pp.257-261.
@

Bedau, M.

(1997): Weak emergence. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp.375-399.
@

Bedford, E.

(1957): Emotions. In: 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society ', vol. 57, pp.281-304.
@

Beebee, H.

(2002): Transfer of warrant, begging the question, and semantic externalism . In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 51, pp.356-74.
@

Beer, C. G.

(1992): Conceptual issues in cognitive ethology. In: ' Advances in the Study of Behavior', vol. 21, pp.69-109.
@

Beer, R.

(1995): A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction. In: 'Artificial Intelligence', vol. 72, pp.173-215.
@

Bekoff, M.

(1999): Social cognition: Exchanging and sharing information on the run. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 51, pp.617-632.
@

Bekoff, M.; Jamieson, D.

(1996): Readings in Animal Cognition. MIT Press.
@

Beloff, J.

(1965): The identity hypothesis: A critique. In: J. R. Smythies (Ed.): 'Brain and Mind'. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
@

Ben-Yami, H.

(1993): A note on the Chinese room. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 95, pp.169-72.
@

Ben-Yami, H.

(1997): Against characterizing mental states as propositional attitudes . In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 186, pp.84-89.
@

Ben-Yami, H.

(1999): An argument against functionalism. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 77, pp.320-324.
@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(1987): The nature of emotions. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 52, pp.393-409.
@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(1990): Describing the emotions. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 3, pp.305-17.
@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(1992): Emotional and moral evaluations. In: 'Metaphilosophy ', vol. 23, pp.214-29.
@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(2003): The logic of emotions. In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): ' Philosophy and the Emotions'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Ben-Ze'ev, A.

(2004): Emotion as a subtle mental mode. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Ben-Zeev, A.

(1986): Two approaches to memory. In: ' Philosophical Investigations', vol. 9, pp.288-301.
@

Benacerraf, P.

(1967): God, the Devil, and Godel. In: 'Monist ', vol. 51, pp.9-32.
@

Benejam, A.

(2003): Thought experiments and semantic competence. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Benn, S.

(1988): A Theory of Freedom. Cambridge University Press.
@

Benner, D. G.; Evans, C. S.

(1984): Unity and multiplicity in hypnosis, commissurotomy, and multiple personality disorder. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 5, pp.423-431.
@

Bennett, J.

(1991): Analysis without noise. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): ' Mind and Common Sense'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Bennett, J.

(1991): Folk-psychological explanations. In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): ' The Future of Folk Psychology'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Bennett, K.

(2003): Why the exclusion problem seems intractable and how, just maybe, to tract it. In: 'Nous ', vol. 37, pp.471-97.
@

Bennett, K.

(2004): Global supervenience and dependence. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 68, pp.501-529.
@

Bennett, L. J.

(1990): Modularity of mind revisited. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 41, pp.429-36.
@

Benson, S.

(1987): Freedom and value. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 84, pp.465-87.
@

Benson, S.

(1994): Free agency and self-worth. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 91, pp.650-58.
@

Benstein, M.

(1992): Fatalism. University of Nebraska Press.
@

Bentall, R.

(2003): Madness Explained. Allen Lane.
@

Berenda, C. W.

(1953): On emergence and prediction. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 50, pp.269-74.
@

Berg, J.

(1998): First-person authority, externalism, and wh-knowledge. In: 'Dialectica', vol. 52, pp.41-44.
@

Bergadano, F.

(1993): Machine learning and the foundations of inductive inference. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 3, pp.31-51.
@

Bergmann, F.

(1977): On Being Free. University of Notre Dame Press.
@

Bergmann, G.

(1944): Holism, historicism, and emergence. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 11, pp.209-21.
@

Bergson, H.

(1991): Matter and memory. In: '1991'.
@

Bergstrom, C.; Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1998): On the evolution of behavioral complexity in individuals and populations. In: 'Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 13, pp.205-31.
@

Berkeley, I.

(2000): What the #$! is a subsymbol?. In: 'Minds and machines ', vol. 10, pp.1-14.
@

Bermudez, J.

(2002): Rationality and psychological explanation without language. In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature'. Clarendon.
@

Bermudez, J.

(2005): Philosophy of Psychology. Routledge.
@

Bermudez, J. L.

(1999): Naturalism and conceptual norms. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.77-85.
@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2001): Normativity and rationality in delusional psychiatric disorders . In: 'Mind & Language,', vol. 16.
@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2003): The elusiveness thesis, immunity to error through misidentification, and privileged access. In: B. Gertler (Ed.): 'Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge'. Ashgate.
@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2003): The domain of folk psychology. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Minds and Persons'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2003): Thinking Without Words. Oxford University Press.
@

Bermudez, J. L.

(2003): Ascribing thoughts to non-linguistic creatures. In: 'Facta Philosophica', vol. 5, pp.313-34.
@

Bermudez, J. L.; Marcel, A.; Eilan, N.

(1995): The Body and the Self. MIT Press.
@

Bernecker, S.

(1996): Davidson on first-person authority and externalism. In: 'Inquiry', vol. 39, pp.121-39.
@

Bernecker, S.

(1996): Externalism and the attitudinal component of self-knowledge. In: 'Nous', vol. 30, pp.262-75.
@

Bernecker, S.

(1998): Self-knowledge and closure. In: P. Ludlow; N. Martin (Ed.): 'Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. CSLI.
@

Bernecker, S.

(2004): Memory and externalism. In: ' Philosophical and Phenomenological Research', vol. 69.
@

Bernier, P.

(1993): Narrow content, context of thought, and asymmetric dependence. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 8, pp.327-42.
@

Bernier, P.

(2002): From simulation to theory. In (J. Dokic & J. In: '2002'.
@

Bernstein, M.

(1995): Kanean libertarianism. In: ' Southwest Philosophical Review', vol. 11, pp.151-57.
@

Bernstein, M.

(2002): Fatalism. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Bernstein, R.

(1968): The challenge of scientific materialism. In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 8, pp.252-75.
@

Berofsky, B.

(1966): Free Will and Determinism. Harper and Row.
@

Berofsky, B.

(1971): Determinism. Princeton University Press.
@

Berofsky, B.

(1987): Freedom from Necessity: The Metaphysical Basis of Responsibility . Routledge.
@

Berofsky, B.

(2000): Ultimate rsponsibility in a determined world. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 60, pp.135-40.
@

Berofsky, B.

(2002): Ifs, cans, and free will: The issues. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Berrios, G.

(1991): Delusions as 'wrong beliefs': A conceptual history. In: 'British Journal of Psychiatry,', vol. 159.
@

Bertocci, P. A.

(1978): The essence of a person. In: 'Monist ', vol. 61, pp.28-41.
@

Bertolet, R.

(1994): Saving eliminativism. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 7, pp.87-100.
@

Bestor, T. W.

(1979): Gilbert Ryle and the adverbial theory of mind. In: ' Personalist', vol. 60, pp.233-42.
@

Bestor, T. W.

(1991): Naturalizing semantics: New insights or old folly?. In: 'Inquiry', vol. 34, pp.285-310.
@

Bickhard, M.

(1993): Representational content in humans and machines. In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 5, pp.285-33.
@

Bickhard, M.

(1996): Troubles with computationalism. In: W. O'Donahue; R. Kitchener (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of Psychology'. Sage Publications.
@

Bickhard, M. H.

(2004): The dynamic emergence of representation. In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind'. Elsevier.
@

Bickle, J.

(1992): Revisionary physicalism. In: 'Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 7, pp.411-30.
@

Bickle, J.

(1992): Multiple realizability and psychophysical reduction. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.47-58.
@

Bickle, J.

(1992): Mental anomaly and the new mind-brain reductionism. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 59, pp.217-30.
@

Bickle, J.

(1993): Connectionism, eliminativism, and the semantic view of theories. In: '1993'.
@

Bickle, J.

(1995): Connectionism, reduction, and multiple realizability. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.29-39.
@

Bickle, J.

(1995): Psychoneural reduction of the genuinely cognitive: Some accomplished facts. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 8, pp.265-85.
@

Bickle, J.

(1995): Connectionism, reduction, and multiple realizability. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.29-39.
@

Bickle, J.

(1996): New wave psychophysical reductionism and the methodological caveats . In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.57-78.
@

Bickle, J.

(1997): Psychoneural Reductionism: The New Wave. MIT Press.
@

Bickle, J.

(2001): New wave metascience: Replies to Beckermann, Maloney, and Stephan . In: 'Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 61, pp.285-293.
@

Bickle, J.

(2002): Philosophy of mind and the sciences. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Bigelow, J. Collins, J.; Pargetter, R.

(1990): Colouring in the world. In: ' Mind', vol. 99, pp.279-88.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(1987): An externalist account of psychological content. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 15, pp.191-226.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(1989): Realism without internalism: A critique of Searle on intentionality . In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 86, pp.57-72.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(1992): Can externalism be reconciled with self-knowledge?. In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 20, pp.233-68.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(1992): Belief and Meaning: The Unity and Locality of Mental Content. Blackwell.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(1993): Norms and meaning. In: R. Stoecker (Ed.): ' Reflecting Davidson'. de Gruyter.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(1994): Other minds. In: J. Dancy; E. Sosa (Ed.): ' A Companion to Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(1998): Why holism is harmless and necessary. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 12, pp.105-126.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(2000): Self-knowledge and resentment. In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Bilgrami, A.

(2003): A trilemma for redeployment. In: 'Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp.22-30.
@

Birnbacher, D.

(1995): Artificial consciousness. In: T. Metzinger (Ed.): ' Conscious Experience'. Ferdinand Schoningh.
@

Birnbaum, L.

(1991): Rigor mortis: A response to Nilsson's `Logic and artificial intelligence'. In: 'Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 47, pp.57-78.
@

Biro, J. I.

(1981): Persons as corporate entities and corporations as persons. In: 'Nature and System', vol. 3, pp.173-80.
@

Biro, J. I.

(1992): In defense of social content. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 67, pp.277-93.
@

Biro, J. I.; Shahan, R. W.

(1982): Mind, Brain and Function. Oklahoma University Press.
@

Biro, J.; Ludwig, K.

(1994): Are there more than minimal a priori limits on irrationality? . In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 72, pp.89-102.
@

Bishop, J.

(1983): Agent-causation. In: 'Mind', vol. 92, pp.61-79.
@

Bishop, J.

(1986): Is agent-causality a conceptal primitive?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 67, pp.225-47.
@

Bishop, J.

(1993): Compatibilism and the free will defense. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 71, pp.104-20.
@

Bishop, M.

(2002): Counterfactuals cannot count: A rejoinder to David Chalmers. In: 'Consciousness and Cognition', vol. 11, pp.642-52.
@

Bishop, M.

(2003): Dancing with pixies: Strong artificial intelligence and panpsychism . In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): ' Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Bishop, M. A.

(2002): The theory theory thrice over: The child as scientist, superscientist, or social institution?. In: ' Studies in History and Philosophy of Science', vol. 33, pp.121-36.
@

Bishop, R. C.

(2002): Chaos, indeterminism, and free will. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Blachowicz, J.

(1997): Analog representation beyond mental imagery. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 94, pp.55-84.
@

Blachowicz, J.

(1997): Analog representation beyond mental imagery. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 94, pp.55-84.
@

Blackburn, S.

(1984): The individual strikes back. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 58.
@

Blackburn, S.

(1984): Supervenience revisited. In: I. Hacking (Ed.): ' Exercises in Analysis: Essays by Students of Casimir Lewy'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Blackburn, S.

(1991): Losing your mind: Physics, identity, and folk burglar prevention . In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): 'The Future of Folk Psychology'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Blackburn, S.

(1992): Theory, observation, and drama. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 7.
@

Blackburn, S.

(1998): Ruling Passions. Oxford University Press.
@

Blackman, L. L.

(2002): Mind as intentionality alone. In: 'Metaphysica ', vol. 3, no.2, pp.41-64.
@

Block, N.

(1978): Troubles with functionalism. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 9, pp.261-325.
@

Block, N.

(1980): Functionalism. In: N. Block (Ed.): ' Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology'. @

Block, N.

(1981): Psychologism and behaviorism. In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 90, pp.5-43.
@

Block, N.

(1981): Imagery. MIT Press.
@

Block, N.

(1983): Mental pictures and cognitive science. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 93, pp.499-542.
@

Block, N.

(1983): The photographic fallacy in the debate about mental imagery. In: 'Nous', vol. 17, pp.651-62.
@

Block, N.

(1986): Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 10, pp.615-78.
@

Block, N.

(1988): Functional role and truth conditions. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 61, pp.157-181.
@

Block, N.

(1989): Can the mind change the world?. In: G. Boolos (Ed.): ' Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Block, N.

(1990): The computer model of mind. In: D. Osherson; E. Smith (Ed.): ' An Invitation to Cognitive Science'. @

Block, N.

(1991): What narrow content is not. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Block, N.

(1995): Ruritania revisited. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Content'. Ridgeview.
@

Block, N.

(1995): An argument for holism. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 95, pp.151-70.
@

Block, N.

(1995): Reply: Causation and two kinds of laws. In: C. Macdonald; G. Macdonald (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Psychology: Debates on Psychological Explanation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Block, N.

(1997): Anti-reductionism slaps back. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 11, pp.107-32.
@

Block, N.

(2003): Do causal powers drain away. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 67, pp.133-150.
@

Block, N.

(2003): Searle's arguments against cognitive science. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Block, N.; Flanagan, O.; Guzeldere, G.

(1997): The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. MIT Press.
@

Block, N.; Fodor, J. A.

(1972): What psychological states are not. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 81, pp.159-81.
@

Bloor, D.

(1997): Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions. Routledge.
@

Blum, A.

(1991): A note on pleasure. In: 'Journal of Value Inquiry ', vol. 25, pp.367-70.
@

Blumenfeld, D.

(1971): The principle of alternate possibilities. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 67, pp.339-44.
@

Blumenfeld, D.

(1988): Freedom and mind control. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 25, pp.215-27.
@

Blumenfeld, J-B.

(1979): Phenomenal properties and the identity theory. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 63, pp.485-93.
@

Blunt, P. K.

(1992): A defense of folk psychology. In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 32, pp.487-98.
@

Bodansky, E.

(1987): Parfit on selves and their interests. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 47, pp.47-50.
@

Boden, M.

(1984): What is computational psychology?. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 58, pp.17-35.
@

Boden, M.

(1988): Escaping from the Chinese Room. In: ' Computer Models of Mind'.
@

Boden, M.

(2001): The philosopgt of cognitive science. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Philosophy at the New Millenium'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Boden, M.

(2003): The Creative Mind. Routledge.
@

Boden, M. A.

(1994): Multiple personality and computational models. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 37, pp.103-114.
@

Boer, de, R.

(1976): Cartesian categories in mind-body identity theories. In: 'Philosophical Forum', vol. 7, pp.139-58.
@

Bogdan, R.

(1986): Belief: Form, Content, and Function. Oxford University Press.
@

Bogdan, R.

(2000): Minding Minds: Evolving a Reflexive Mind by Interpreting Others. MIT Press.
@

Bogdan, R. G.

(1991): Mind and Common Sense: Philosophical Essays on Commonsense Psychology . Cambridge University Press.
@

Bogdan, R. G.

(2003): Minding Minds: Evolving a Reflexive Mind by Interpreting Others . MIT Press.
@

Bogdan, R. J.

(1986): The manufacture of belief. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): ' Belief: Form, Content, and Function'. Oxford University Press.
@

Bogdan, R. J.

(1987): Mind, content and information. In: '1987'.
@

Bogdan, R. J.

(1988): Information and semantic cognition: An ontological account. In: '1988'.
@

Bogdan, R. J.

(1989): Does semantics run the psyche?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 49, pp.687-700.
@

Bogen, J.

(2001): Functional imaging evidence: Some epistemic hotspots. In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences'. University of Pittsburgh Press.
@

Boghossian, P,

(1992): Externalism and inference. In: 'Philosophical Issues ', vol. 2, pp.11-28.
@

Boghossian, P.

(1989): Content and self-knowledge. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 17, pp.5-26.
@

Boghossian, P.

(1989): The rule-following considerations. In: 'Mind ', vol. 98, pp.507-49.
@

Boghossian, P.

(1990): The status of content. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 99, pp.157-84.
@

Boghossian, P.

(1991): Naturalizing content. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): ' Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Boghossian, P.

(1991): The status of content revisited. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 71, pp.264-78.
@

Boghossian, P.

(1994): The transparency of mental content. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 8, pp.33-50.
@

Boghossian, P.

(1997): What the externalist can know a priori. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 97, pp.161-75.
@

Boghossian, P.

(2002): Seeking the real. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 108, pp.223-38.
@

Boghossian, P.

(2003): The normativity of content. In: 'Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp.31-45.
@

Boghossian, P. A.

(1994): Inferential-role semantics and the analytic/synthetic distinction . In: '1994'.
@

Boghossian, P.; Velleman, J. D.

(1989): Color as a secondary quality. In: ' Mind', vol. 98, pp.81-103.
@

Boghossian, P.; Velleman, J. D.

(1991): Physicalist theories of color. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 100, pp.67-106.
@

Bok, H.

(1998): Freedom and Responsibility. Princeton University Press.
@

Bolender, J.

(1995): Is multiple realizability compatible with antireductionism?. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 33, pp.129-42.
@

Bolender, J.

(2003): A farewell to isms. In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): ' Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

BonJour, L.

(1976): Deeterminism, libertarianism, and agent causation. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 14, pp.145-56.
@

Bonevac, D.

(1988): Supervenience and ontology. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 25, pp.37-47.
@

Bonjour, L.

(1991): Is thought a symbolic process?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 89, pp.331-52.
@

Bontly, T.

(2001): Should intentionality be naturalized?. In: D. Walsh (Ed.): ' Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Bontly, T.

(2002): The supervenience argument generalizes. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 109, pp.75-96.
@

Bontly, T. D.

(2002): The supervenience argument generalizes. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 109, pp.75-96.
@

Borges, M.

(2004): What can Kant teach us about emotions. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 101, pp.140-158.
@

Borst, C. V.

(1970): The Mind/Brain Identity Theory. Macmillan.
@

Bortolotti, L.

(2005): Delusions and the background of rationality. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 20, pp.189-208.
@

Botterell, A.

(2002): Physicalism, supervenience, and dependence: a reply to Campbell . In: 'Dialogue', vol. 41, pp.155-161.
@

Botterill, G.

(1994): Beliefs, functionally discrete states, and connectionist networks . In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 45, pp.899-906.
@

Botterill, G.

(1996): Folk psychology and theoretical status. In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Bovens, L.

(1994): Principles of supervenience. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 72, pp.294-301.
@

Bovens, L.

(1999): Do beliefs supervene on degrees of confidence?. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Belief, Cognition, and the Will'. Tilburg University Press.
@

Bowie, G.

(1982): Lucas' number is finally up. In: ' Journal of Philosophy Logic,', vol. 11, pp.279-85.
@

Bowman, A.

(1953): Knowledge of other minds. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 50, pp.328-32.
@

Boyd, R.

(1980): Materialism without reductionism: What physicalism does not entail. In: N. Block (Ed.): 'Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology'.
@

Boyd, R.

(1999): Kinds, complexity, and multiple realization. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 95, pp.67-98.
@

Boyer, D.

(1983): J. R. Lucas, Kurt Godel, and Fred Astaire. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 33, pp.147-59.
@

Boyle, C. F.

(1994): Computation as an intrinsic property. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.451-67.
@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.

(2004): Masters of our meanings. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 118, pp.133-52.
@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Fitzpatrick, J.

(1990): Explanation and the language of thought . In: 'Synthese', vol. 83, pp.3-29.
@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Jackson, F.

(1997): The teleological theory of content. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 75, pp.474-89.
@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Jackson, F.

(1997): Philosophy of Mind and Cognition. Blackwell.
@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Jackson, F.

(2002): A pyrrhic victory for teleonomy. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 80, pp.372-77.
@

Braddon-Mitchell, D.; Jackson, K.

(1999): The divide-and-conquer path to analytic functionalism. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 26, pp.71-89.
@

Bradley, M. C.

(1963): Sensations, brain-processes, and colours. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 41, pp.385-93.
@

Bradshaw, D. E.

(1991): Connectionism and the specter of representationalism. In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Braithwaite, M.

(1949): Causal laws in psychology. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 23, pp.45-60.
@

Brakel, van, J.

(1991): Meaning, prototypes, and the future of cognitive science. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.233-57.
@

Brakel, van, J.

(1996): Interdiscourse or supervenience relations: The primacy of the manifest image. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 106, pp.253-97.
@

Brakel, van, J.

(2005): Supervenience and anomalous monism. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 53, pp.3-24.
@

Brandom, R.

(1994): Reasoning and representing. In: M. Michael; J. O'Leary-Hawthorne (Ed.): 'Philosophy in Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Brandom, R.

(1994): Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment . Harvard University Press.
@

Brandom, R.

(2001): Modality, normativity, and intentionality. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 63, pp.611-23.
@

Brandt, R.

(1960): Doubts about the identity theory. In: S. Hook (Ed.): ' Dimensions of Mind'. New York University Press.
@

Brandt, R.; Kim, J.

(1967): The logic of the identity theory. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 66, pp.515-537.
@

Bratman, M.

(1990): Dretske's desires. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 50, pp.795-800.
@

Bratman, M.

(2003): A desire of one's own. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 100, pp.221-42.
@

Braude, S. E.

(1991): First-person Plural: Multiple Personality and the Philosophy of Mind . Routledge.
@

Braude, S. E.

(1996): Multiple personality disorder and moral responsibility. In: 'Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 3, pp.37-54.
@

Braun, D.

(1991): Content, causation, and cognitive science. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 69, pp.375-89.
@

Braun, D.

(1995): Causally relevant properties. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.447-75.
@

Breazeal, C.; Brooks, R.

(2004): Robot emotions: A functional perspective. In: J. Fellous (Ed.): 'Who Needs Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Brennan, A.

(1982): Personal identity and personal survival. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 42, pp.44-50.
@

Brennan, A.

(1984): Survival. In: 'Synthese', vol. 59, pp.339-62.
@

Brennan, A.

(1987): Discontinuity and identity. In: 'Nous ', vol. 21, pp.241-60.
@

Brennan, A.

(1988): Conditions of Identity: A Study of Identity and Survival. Oxford University Press.
@

Brennan, A. A.

(1987): Survival and importance. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 47, pp.225-30.
@

Brewer, B.

(1995): Compulsion by reason (Mental Causation II). In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 69, pp.237-53.
@

Bricke, J.

(1975): Interaction and physiology. In: 'Mind ', vol. 84, pp.255-9.
@

Bricke, J.

(2000): Desires, passions, and evaluations. In: ' Southwest Philosophy Review', vol. 16, pp.59-65.
@

Bridges, J.

(2005): Davidson's transcendental externalism. In: '2005'.
@

Bridges, J.

(2005): Does informational semantics commit Euthypho's fallacy. In: '2005'.
@

Bringsjord, S.

(1991): Is the connectionist-logicist debate one of AI's wonderful red herrings?. In: ' Journal of Theoretical and Experimental Artificial Intelligence', vol. 3, pp.319-49.
@

Bringsjord, S.

(1992): What Robots Can and Can't Be. Kluwer.
@

Bringsjord, S.

(1994): Could, how could we tell if, and should -- androids have inner lives? . In: K. M. Ford; C. Glymour; P. Hayes (Ed.): 'Android Epistemology'. MIT Press.
@

Bringsjord, S.

(1994): Computation, among other things, is beneath us. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.469-88.
@

Bringsjord, S.

(1998): Cognition is not computation: The argument from irreversibility . In: '1998'.
@

Bringsjord, S.

(2001): Creativity, the Turing test, and the (better) Lovelace test. In: 'Minds & Machines', vol. 11, pp.3-27.
@

Bringsjord, S.; Bello, P.; Ferrucci, D.

(2001): Creativity, the Turing test, and the (better) Lovelace test. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 11, pp.3-27.
@

Bringsjord, S.; Noel, R.

(2003): Real robots and the missing thought-experiment in the Chinese room dialectic. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Bringsjord, S.; Zenzen, M.

(1997): Cognition is not computation: The argument from irreversibility. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 113, pp.285-320.
@

Broackes, J.

(1992): The autonomy of colour. In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): ' Reduction, Explanation, and Realism'. Oxford University Press.
@

Broackes, J.

(1997): The Nature of Colour. Routledge.
@

Broad, C. D.

(1925): The Mind and its Place in Nature. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
@

Broad, C. D.

(1971): Emotion and sentiment. In: ' Critical Essays in Moral Theory'.
@

Broadbent, D.

(1985): A question of levels: Comment on McClelland and Rumelhart. In: 'Journal of Experimental Psychology: General', vol. 114, pp.189-92.
@

Brodbeck, M.

(1966): Mental and physical: Identity versus sameness. In: P. Feyerabend; G. Maxwell (Ed.): ' Mind, Matter, and Method: Essays in Philosophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl'. University of Minnesota Press.
@

Brook, A.; Stainton, R.

(1997): Fodor's new theory of content and computation. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.459-74.
@

Brook, D.

(1992): Substantial mind. In: 'South African Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 1, pp.15-21.
@

Brooks, D. H. M.

(1986): Group minds. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 64, pp.456-70.
@

Brooks, D. H. M.

(1994): How to perform a reduction. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 54, pp.803-14.
@

Brooks, R.

(1991): Intelligence without representation. In: ' Artificial Intelligence', vol. 47, pp.139-159.
@

Brown, C.

(1993): Belief states and narrow content. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 8, pp.343-67.
@

Brown, C.

(2002): Narrow mental content. In: '2002'.
@

Brown, D. J.

(1993): Swampman of La Mancha. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.327-48.
@

Brown, D. J.

(1996): A furry tile about mental representation. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 185, pp.448-66.
@

Brown, H.

(1986): Sellars, concepts, and conceptual change. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 68, pp.275-307.
@

Brown, J.

(1995): The incompatibility of anti-individualism and privileged access. In: 'Analysis', vol. 55, pp.149-56.
@

Brown, J.

(1998): Natural kind terms and recognitional capacities. In: 'Mind ', vol. 107, pp.275-303.
@

Brown, J.

(2000): Critical reasoning, understanding and self-knowledge. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 61, pp.659-676.
@

Brown, J.

(2000): Reliabilism, knowledge, and mental content. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 100, pp.115-35.
@

Brown, J.

(2001): Anti-individualism and agnosticism. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 61, pp.213-24.
@

Brown, J.

(2003): The reductio argument and transmission of warrant. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Brown, M. T.

(2001): Multiple personality and personal identity. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.435-47.
@

Brown, R.; Herrstein, R.

(1981): Icons and images. In: N. Block (Ed.): 'Imagery '. MIT Press.
@

Browne, D.

(1996): Cognitive versatility. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 6, pp.507-23.
@

Bruckner, A.

(2003): Two transcendental arguments concerning self-knowledge. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Bruecker, A.

(1998): Shoemaker on second-order belief. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 58, pp.361-64.
@

Brueckner A.

(2004): Brewer on the McKinsey problem. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 64, pp.41-43.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1990): Scepticism about knowledge of content. In: 'Mind ', vol. 99, pp.447-51.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1992): What an anti-individualist knows a priori. In: ' Analysis', vol. 52, pp.111-18.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1992): Semantic answers to skepticism. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 73, pp.200-19.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1993): Skepticism and externalism. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 22, pp.169-71.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1993): Parfit on what matters in survival. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 70, pp.1-22.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1994): Knowledge of content and knowledge of the world. In: ' Philosophical Review:', vol. 103.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1995): The characteristic thesis of anti-individualism. In: ' Analysis', vol. 55, pp.146-48.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1995): Trying to get outside your own skin. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 23, pp.79-111.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1997): Externalism and memory. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 78, pp.1-12.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1997): Is scepticism about self-knowledge incoherent?. In: ' Analysis', vol. 4, pp.287-90.
@

Brueckner, A.

(1999): Two recent approaches to self-knowledge. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 13, pp.251-71.
@

Brueckner, A.

(2000): Externalism and the a prioricity of self-knowledge. In: 'Analysis', vol. 60, pp.132-136.
@

Brueckner, A.

(2000): Ambiguity and knowledge of content. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 60, pp.257-60.
@

Brueckner, A.

(2001): Defending Burge's thought experiment. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 55, pp.387-391.
@

Brueckner, A.

(2001): A priori knowledge of the world not easily available. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 104, pp.109-114.
@

Brueckner, A.

(2001): Problems for a recent account of introspective knowledge. In: '2001'.
@

Brueckner, A.

(2002): Anti-individualism and analyticity. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 62, pp.87-91.
@

Brueckner, A.

(2003): Contents just aren't in the head. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 58, pp.1-6.
@

Brueckner, A.

(2005): Noordhof on McKinsey-Brown. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 65.
@

Bruner, J.

(1957): On perceptual readiness. In: 'Psychological Review ', vol. 65, pp.14-21.
@

Bruns, M.; Soldati, G.

(1997): Object-dependent and property-dependent concepts. In: 'Dialectica', vol. 48, pp.185-208.
@

Bruntrup, G.

(1998): Is psychophysical emergentism committed to dualism? The causal efficacy of emergent mental properties. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 48, pp.133-51.
@

Bub, J.

(1994): Testing models of cognition through the analysis of brain-damaged patients . In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 45, pp.837-55.
@

Buchanan, B.

(1988): AI as an experimental science. In: J. Fetzer (Ed.): ' Aspects of AI'. D.
@

Buck, R.

(1962): Non-other minds. In: R. Butler (Ed.): 'Analytic Philosophy '. Barnes and Noble.
@

Buckley, J.; Hall, L.

(1999): Self-knowledge and embodiment. In: ' Southwest Philosophy Review', vol. 15.
@

Buckley, R.

(2001): Physicalism and the problem of mental causation. In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 26, pp.155-174.
@

Budd, M.

(1984): Wittgenstein on meaning, interpretation and rules. In: ' Synthese', vol. 58.
@

Buekens, F.

(1994): Externalism, content, and causal histories. In: ' Dialectica', vol. 48, pp.267-86.
@

Buford, T. O.

(1970): Essays on Other Minds. University of Illinois Press.
@

Buller, D. J.

(1992): "Narrow"-minded breeds inaction. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.59-70.
@

Buller, D. J.

(1993): Confirmation and the computational paradigm, or, why do you think they call it artificial intelligence?. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 3, pp.155-81.
@

Buller, D. J.

(1997): Individualism and evolutionary psychology (or: In defense of "narrow" functions). In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 64, pp.74-95.
@

Buller, D. J.

(1999): DeFreuding evolutionary psychology: Adaptation and human motivation . In: V. Hardcastle (Ed.): 'Where Biology Meets Philosophy'. MIT Press.
@

Buller, D. J.

(2000): A guided tour of evolutionary psychology. In: '2000 '.
@

Buller, D. J.

(2005): Adapting Minds: Evolutionary Psychology and the Persistent Quest for Human Nature. MIT Press.
@

Buller, D. J.

(2005): Evolutionary psychology: The emperor's new paradigm. In: '2005'.
@

Buller, D. J.; Hardcastle, V. G.

(2000): Evolutionary psychology, meet developmental neurobiology: Against promiscuous modularity. In: ' Brain and Mind', vol. 1, pp.307-25.
@

Bundy, A.

(1990): What kind of field is AI?. In: D. Partridge; Y. Wilks (Ed.): ' The Foundations of Artificial Intelligence: A Sourcebook'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Bunge, M.

(1977): Emergence and the mind. In: 'Neuroscience ', vol. 2, pp.501-9.
@

Bunzl, M.

(1987): Reductionism and the mental. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 24, pp.181-9.
@

Burge, T.

(1979): Individualism and the mental. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 4, pp.73-122.
@

Burge, T.

(1982): Other bodies. In: A. Woodfield (Ed.): 'Thought and Object '. Oxford University Press.
@

Burge, T.

(1982): Two thought experiments reviewed. In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic', vol. 23, pp.284-94.
@

Burge, T.

(1986): Intellectual norms and foundations of mind. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 83, pp.697-720.
@

Burge, T.

(1986): Individualism and psychology. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 95, pp.3-45.
@

Burge, T.

(1986): Individualism and psychology. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 95, pp.3-45.
@

Burge, T.

(1986): Intellectual norms and foundations of mind. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 83, pp.697-720.
@

Burge, T.

(1988): Individualism and self-knowledge. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 85, pp.649-63.
@

Burge, T.

(1989): Individuation and causation in psychology. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 707, pp.303-22.
@

Burge, T.

(1992): Philosophy of language and mind: 1950-1990. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 100, pp.3-52.
@

Burge, T.

(1993): Concepts, definitions, and meaning. In: 'Metaphilosophy ', vol. 24, pp.309-25.
@

Burge, T.

(1993): Mind-body causation and explanatory practice. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Burge, T.

(1995): Intentional properties and causation. In: C. Macdonald; G. Macdonald (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Psychology: Debates about Psychological Explanation'. Blackwell.
@

Burge, T.

(1996): Our entitlement to self-knowledge. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 96, pp.91-116.
@

Burge, T.

(1998): Memory and self-knowledge. In: P. Ludlow; N. Martin (Ed.): ' Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. CSLI.
@

Burge, T.

(1999): A century of deflation and a moment about self-knowledge. In: 'Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 73, pp.25-46.
@

Burge, T.

(2000): Reason and the first person. In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2003): Davidson and forms of anti-individualism: Reply to Hahn. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2003): Descartes, bare concepts, and anti-individualism: Reply to Normore. In (M. Hahn & B. Ramberg, eds) Reflections and Replies. MIT Press. Burge, T. 2003. The thought experiments: Reply to Do In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2003): The indexical strategy: Reply to Owens. In (M. Hahn & B. Ramberg, eds) Reflections and Replies. MIT Press. Burge, T. 2003. Psychology and the environment: Reply to Chomsky . In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2003): Replies from Tyler Burge. In (M. Frapolli & E. Romero, eds) Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind. CSLI. Donnellan, K. 2003. Burge's thought experiments . In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2003): Mental agency in authoritative self-knowledge: Reply to Kobes. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2003): Some reflections on scepticism: Reply to Stroud. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2003): Epiphenomenalism: Reply to Dretske. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2003): Concepts, conceptions, reflective understanding: Reply to Peacocke . In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Burge, T.

(2004): Memory and persons. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 112.
@

Burgos, J.

(2004): Realism about behavior. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 32, pp.69-95.
@

Burks, A. W.

(1973): Logic, computers, and men. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 46, pp.39-57.
@

Bush, E.

(1974): Rorty revisited. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 25, pp.33-42.
@

Bushnell, D. E.

(1993): Identity, psychological continuity, and rationality. In: 'Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 18, pp.15-24.
@

Buss, D. M.

(1999): Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind. Allyn and Bacon.
@

Butler, K.

(1991): Towards a connectionist cognitive architecture. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 6, pp.252-72.
@

Butler, K.

(1992): The physiology of desire. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 13, pp.69-88.
@

Butler, K.

(1993): Connectionism, classical cognitivism, and the relation between cognitive and implementational levels of analysis . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 6, pp.321-33.
@

Butler, K.

(1993): On Clark on systematicity and connectionism. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 44, pp.37-44.
@

Butler, K.

(1994): Neural constraints in cognitive science. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.129-62.
@

Butler, K.

(1995): Content, context, and compositionality. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 10, pp.3-24.
@

Butler, K.

(1995): Compositionality in cognitive models: The real issue. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 78, pp.153-62.
@

Butler, K.

(1995): Representation and computation in a deflationary assessment of connectionist cognitive science. In: ' Synthese', vol. 104, pp.71-97.
@

Butler, K.

(1996): Content, causal powers, and context. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 63, pp.105-14.
@

Butler, K.

(1996): Individualism and Marr's computational theory of vision. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 11, pp.313-37.
@

Butler, K.

(1996): Content, computation, and individualism in vision theory. In: 'Analysis', vol. 56, pp.146-54.
@

Butler, K.

(1997): Externalism, internalism, and knowledge of content. In: ' philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 57, pp.773-800.
@

Butler, K.

(1998): Internal Affairs: Making Room for Psychosemantic Internalism. Kluwer.
@

Butler, K.

(1998): Content, computation, and individuation. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 114, pp.277-92.
@

Butler, K.

(1998): Externalism and skepticism. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 37, pp.13-34.
@

Butler, K.

(2000): Problems for semantic externalism and a priori refutations of skeptical arguments. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 54, pp.29-49.
@

Buttazzo, G.

(2001): Artificial consciousness: Utopia or real possibility?. In: 'Computer', vol. 34, pp.24-30.
@

Button, G.; Coulter, J.; Lee, J. R. E.; Sharrock, W.

(1995): Computers, Minds, and Conduct . Polity Press.
@

Bynum, T. W.

(1985): Artificial intelligence, biology, and intentional states. In: 'Metaphilosophy', vol. 16, pp.355-77.
@

Byrne, A.

(1996): On misinterpreting Kripke's Wittgenstein. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56.
@

Byrne, A.

(1998): Interpretivism. In: 'European Review of Philosophy ', vol. 3.
@

Byrne, A.

(2001): Do colors look like dispositions? Reply to Langsam and others. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 51.
@

Byrne, A.

(2002): Yes, Virginia, lemons are yellow. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 108, pp.213-22.
@

Byrne, A.

(2003): Color and similarity. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', 66:641-665. @

Byrne, A.; Hilbert, D. R.

(1997): Readings on Color, Volume 1: The Philosophy of Color. MIT Press.
@

Byrne, A.; Hilbert, D. R.

(1997): Readings on Color, Volume 2: The Science of Color. MIT Press.
@

Byrne, A.; Hilbert, D. R.

(1997): Colors and reflectances. In: A. Byrne; D. R. Hilbert (Ed.): 'Readings on Color, Volume 1: The Philosophy of Color'. MIT Press.
@

Byrne, A.; Hilbert, D. R.

(2004): Hardin, Tye, and color physicalism. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 101, pp.37-43.
@

Byrne, A.; Pryor, J.

(2006): Bad intensions. In: M. Garcia-Carpintero; J. Macia (Ed.): 'Two-Dimensional Semantics: Foundations and Applications'. Oxford University Press.

C


@

Cain, M. J.

(1999): Fodor's attempt to naturalize mental content. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.520-26.
@

Cain, M. J.

(2000): Individualism, twin scenarios and visual content. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.441-463.
@

Cain, M. J.

(2002): Fodor: Language, Mind, and Philosophy. Polity Press.
@

Calhoun, C.

(2004): Subjectivity and emotion. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Callaway, H. G.

(1992): Meaning holism and semantic realism. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 46, pp.41-59.
@

Callaway, H. G.

(1995): Intentionality naturalized: Continuity, reconstruction, and instrumentalism. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 49, pp.147-68.
@

Calvin, W.

(2004): A Brief History of the Mind: From Apes to Intellect and Beyond. Oxford University Press.
@

Cam, P.

(1978): "Rorty revisited", or "Rorty revised". In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 33, pp.377-86.
@

Cam, P.

(1984): Dennett on intelligent storage. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 45, pp.247-62.
@

Cam, P.

(1987): Propositions about images. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 48, pp.335-8.
@

Cam, P.

(1988): Modularity, rationality, and higher cognition. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 53, pp.279-94.
@

Cam, P.

(1990): Searle on strong AI. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 68, pp.103-8.
@

Cam, P.

(1990): Insularity and the persistence of perceptual illusion. In: ' Analysis', vol. 50, pp.231-5.
@

Campbell, C. A.

(1951): Is "free will" a pseudoproblem?. In: 'Mind ', vol. 60, pp.441-65.
@

Campbell, C. A.

(1953): Ryle on the intellect. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 3, pp.115-38.
@

Campbell, C. A.

(1967): In Defense of Free Will. Allen and Unwin.
@

Campbell, D.

(2005): Joint attention and common knowledge . In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, (eds.); Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds. In: '2005'.
@

Campbell, J.

(1993): A simple view of colour. In: J. Haldane; C. Wright (Ed.); 'Reality, Representation, and Projection'. Oxford University Press.
@

Campbell, J.

(1997): The realism of memory. In: R. Heck (Ed.); ' Language, Thought, and Logic: Essays in Honour of Michael Dummett'. Oxford University Press.
@

Campbell, J.

(1997): The structure of time in autobiographical memory. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.105-17.
@

Campbell, J.

(1999): Immunity to error through misidentification and the meaning of a referring term. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 26, pp.89-104.
@

Campbell, J.

(1999): Schizophrenia, the space of reasons and thinking as a motor process . In: 'Monist', vol. 82.
@

Campbell, J.

(2001): Rationality, meaning, and the analysis of delusion. In: 'Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology,', vol. 8, pp.89-100.
@

Campbell, J.

(2002): Joint attention and simulation. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Campbell, J.

(2002): Berkeley's puzzle. In: T. Gendler; J. Hawthorne (Ed.): ' Conceivability and Possibility'. MIT Press.
@

Campbell, J. K.

(1997): A compatibilist theory of alternate possibilities. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 67, pp.339-44.
@

Campbell, K.

(1969): Colours. In: R. Brown; C. Rollins (Ed.): ' Contemporary Philosophy in Australia'. Humanities Press.
@

Campbell, K.

(1982): The implications of Land's theory of colour vision. In: L. Cohen (Ed.): 'Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science'.
@

Campbell, K.

(1983): Abstract particulars and the philosophy of mind. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 61, pp.129-41.
@

Campbell, K.

(1993): David Armstrong and realism about colour. In: J. Bacon; K. Campbell; L. Reinhardt (Ed.): 'Ontology, Causality, and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Campbell, N.

(1997): The standard objection to anomalous monism. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 75, pp.373-82.
@

Campbell, N.

(1998): Anomalous monism and the charge of epiphenomenalism. In: 'Dialectica', vol. 52, pp.23-39.
@

Campbell, N.

(2002): Physicalism, supervenience, and dependence: a reply to Botterell . In: 'Dialogue', vol. 41, pp.163-167.
@

Campbell, S.

(2000): Strawson, Parfit and impersonality. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 30, pp.207-225.
@

Campbell, S.

(2001): Is connectedess necessary to what mattres in survival?. In: 'Ration', vol. 14, pp.193-202.
@

Campbell, S.

(2001): Persons and substances. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 104, pp.253-67.
@

Campbell, S.

(2004): Rapid psychological change. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 64, pp.256-264.
@

Campbell, S.

(2004): Can you survive a brain-zap?. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 70.
@

Canali, S.

(2004): On the concept of the psychological. In: 'Topoi ', vol. 23, pp.177-86.
@

Candlish, S.

(1970): Mind, brain, and identity. In: 'Mind ', vol. 79, pp.502-18.
@

Candlish, S.

(1975): Mental images and pictorial properties. In: 'Mind ', vol. 84, pp.260-2.
@

Canfield, J.

(1996): The community view. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 105, pp.469-488.
@

Caplain, G.

(1995): Is consciousness a computational property?. In: ' Informatica', vol. 19, pp.615-19.
@

Carleton, L.

(1984): Programs, language understanding, and Searle. In: ' Synthese', vol. 59, pp.219-30.
@

Carlson, E.

(2002): In defense of the Mind argument. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 29, pp.393-400.
@

Carnap, R.

(1959): Psychology in physical language. In: Ayer (Ed.): ' Logical Positivism'. Free Press.
@

Carney, J.

(1971): The compatibility of mind-body identity with dualism. In: '1971'.
@

Carrier, L.

(1973): Professor Shaffer's refutation of behaviourism. In: ' Mind', vol. 80, pp.249-52.
@

Carruthers, P.

(1984): Baker and Hacker's Wittgenstein. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 58, pp.451-79.
@

Carruthers, P.

(1985): Ruling-out realism. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 15, pp.61-78.
@

Carruthers, P.

(1986): Introducing Persons: Theories and Arguments in the Philosophy of Mind . SUNY Press.
@

Carruthers, P.

(1996): Simulation and self-knowledge: A defence of the theory-theory . In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Carruthers, P.

(2000): Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory. Cambridge University Press.
@

Carruthers, P.

(2003): On Fodor's problem. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp.502-523.
@

Carruthers, P.

(2003): Moderately massive modularity. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Mind and Persons'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Carruthers, P.

(2003): The Nature of Mind. Routledge.
@

Carruthers, P.

(2004): Practical reasoning in a modular mind. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.259-278.
@

Carruthers, P.; Smith, P.

(1996): Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge University Press.
@

Carter, W.

(1999): Will I be a dead person?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 59.
@

Carter, W. R.

(1974): On incorrigibility and eliminative materialism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 28, pp.113-21.
@

Cartwright, H. M.

(1987): Ruminations on an account of personal identity. In: J. J. Thomson (Ed.): 'On Being and Saying: Essays on Honor of Richard Cartwright'. MIT Press.
@

Cartwright, H. M.

(1993): On two arguments for the indeterminacy of personal identity . In: 'Synthese', vol. 95, pp.241-273.
@

Cascardi, A. J.

(1984): Remembering. In: 'Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 38, pp.275-302.
@

Case, J.

(2004): Offloading memory to the environment: A quantitative example. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 14, pp.387-89.
@

Casey, E. S.

(1987): Remembering: A Phenomenological Study. Indiana University Press.
@

Casey, E. S.

(2003): Imagination, fantasy, hallucination, and memory. In: J. Philips; J. Morley (Ed.): 'Imagination and its Pathologies'. MIT Press.
@

Cassam, Q.

(1993): Parfit on persons. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 93, pp.17-37.
@

Cassam, Q.

(1994): Self-Knowledge. Oxford University Press.
@

Cassam, Q.

(1995): Introspection and bodily self-ascription. In: J. Bermudez; A. Marcel; N. Eilan (Ed.): 'The Body and the Self'. MIT Press.
@

Cassam, Q.

(1998): Self-knowledge, a priori knowledge, and the cognitive structure of the mind. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Cassam, Q.

(2002): Representing bodies. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 15, pp.315-334.
@

Castaneda, H.

(1962): Criteria, analogy, and knowledge of other minds. In: ' 1962'.
@

Caston, V.

(1997): Epiphenomenalisms, ancient and modern. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 106, pp.309-363.
@

Catalano, J.

(2000): Thinking Matter: Consciousness from Aristotle to Putnam and Sartre . Routledge.
@

Causey, R. L.

(1972): Attribute identities in microreductions. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 69, pp.407-22.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1990): Syntactic transformations on distributed representations. In: 'Connection Science', vol. 2, pp.53-62.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1992): Subsymbolic computation and the Chinese Room. In: J. Dinsmore (Ed.): 'The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1993): Connectionism and compositionality: Why Fodor and Pylyshyn were wrong. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 6, pp.305-319.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1994): A computational foundation for the study of cognition.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1994): On implementing a computation. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.391-402.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1996): The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford University Press.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1996): Supervenience and materialism. In: ' The Conscious Mind'.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1996): Minds, machines, and mathematics. In: 'Psyche ', vol. 2, pp.11-20.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(1996): Does a rock implement every finite-state automaton?. In: 'Synthese', vol. 108, pp.309-33.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2002): The components of content. In: D. Chalmers (Ed.): ' Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings'. Oxford University Press.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2002): On sense and intension. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 16, pp.135-82.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2003): Consciousness and its place in nature. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2003): The nature of narrow content. In: ' Philosophical Issues', vol. 13, pp.46-66.
@

Chalmers, D. J.

(2004): Epistemic two-dimensional semantics. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 118, pp.153-226.
@

Chalmers, D. J.; French, R. M.; Hofstadter, D. R.

(1992): High-level perception, representation, and analogy: A critique of AI methodology. In: '1992'.
@

Chambers, D.; Reisberg, D.

(1985): Can mental images be ambiguous?. In: ' ' Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance', vol. 11, pp.317-28.
@

Chambers, D.; Reisberg, D.

(1992): What an image depicts depends on what an image means . In: 'Cognitive Psychology', vol. 24, pp.145-74.
@

Champlin, T. S.

(1992): Solitary rule-following. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 67, pp.285-306.
@

Chan, D. K.

(2004): Are there extrinsic desires?. In: 'Nous ', vol. 38, pp.326-50.
@

Chandrasekaran, B.; Goel, A.; Allemang, D.

(1988): Connectionism and information-processing abstractions. In: 'AI Magazine', vol. 24.
@

Changeux, J.; Ricoeur, P.

(2002): What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain. Princeton.
@

Chapman, C. R.; Nakakura, Y.; Chapman, C. N.

(2000): Pain and folk theory. In: 'Brain and Mind', vol. 1, pp.209-222.
@

Chappell, T.

(1995): Personal identity, R-relatedness, and the empty question argument . In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 45, pp.88-92.
@

Chappell, T.

(1998): Reductionism about persons; and what matters. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 98, pp.41-58.
@

Chappell, V. C.

(1963): The concept of dreaming. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 13, pp.193-213.
@

Chari, C.

(1963): Further comments on minds, machines and Godel. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 38, pp.175-8.
@

Charland, L. C.

(1995): Feeling and representing: Computational theory and the modularity of affect. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 105, pp.273-301.
@

Charland, L. C.

(1997): Reconciling cognitive and perceptual theories of emotion: A representational proposal. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 64, pp.555-579.
@

Charland, L. C.

(2002): The natural kind status of emotion. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 53, pp.511-37.
@

Charles, D.

(1992): Supervenience, composition, and physicalism. In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism'. Oxford University Press.
@

Chase, J.

(2001): Is externalism about content inconsistent with internalism about justification?. In: ' Australasian Jouenal of Philosophy', vol. 79, pp.227-46.
@

Chater, N. and Oaksford, M.

(2002): The rational analysis of human cognition. In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature'. Clarendon.
@

Chater, N.; Oaksford, M.

(1990): Autonomy, implementation and cognitive architecture: A reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 34, pp.93-107.
@

Chater, N.; Oaksford, M.

(1996): The falsity of folk theories: Implications for psychology and philosophy. In: W. O'Donahue; R. Kitchener (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of Psychology'. Sage Publications.
@

Chater, N.; Vitanyi, P.

(2003): Simplicity: A unifying principle in cognitive science? . In: 'Trends in Cognitive Science', vol. 7, pp.19-22.
@

Chemero, A.

(2002): Reconsidering Ryle: Editor's introduction. In: ' Electronic Journal of Anlaytic Philosophy', vol. 7.
@

Cheney, D. L.; Seyfarth, R. M.

(1990): How Monkeys See the World: Inside the Mind of Another Species. University of Chicago Press.
@

Cheng, K.

(1997): Davidson's action theory and epiphenomenalism. In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 22, pp.81-95.
@

Cherniak, C.

(1981): Minimal rationality. In: 'Mind ', vol. 90, pp.161-83.
@

Cherniak, C.

(1983): Rationality and the structure of memory. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 57, pp.163-86.
@

Cherniak, C.

(1983): Rationality and the structure of human memory. In: ' Synthese', vol. 57, pp.163-86.
@

Cherniak, C.

(1986): Minimal Rationality. MIT Press.
@

Cherniak, C.

(1991): Meta-neuroanatomy: The myth of the unbounded mind/brain. In (E. In: '1991'.
@

Cherniak, C.

(1994): Philosophy and computational neuroanatomy. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 73, pp.89-107.
@

Chien, A. J.

(1996): Why the mind may not be modular. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 6, pp.1-32.
@

Chihara, C.

(1965): What dreams are made of. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 31, pp.145-58.
@

Chihara, C.

(1972): On alleged refutations of mechanism using Godel's incompleteness results . In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 64, pp.507-26.
@

Chihara, C.; Fodor, J.

(1965): Operationalism and ordinary language: A critique of Wittgenstein. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 2, pp.281-95.
@

Child, W.

(1993): Anomalism, uncodifiability, and psychophysical relations. In: '1993'.
@

Child, W.

(2002): Reply to 'Simulation theory and mental concepts'. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Chisholm, R.

(1952): Intentionality and the theory of signs. In: '1952'.
@

Chisholm, R.

(1955): A note on Carnap's meaning analysis. In: '1955'.
@

Chisholm, R.

(1958): Sentences about believing. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 2.
@

Chisholm, R. M.

(1976): Person and Object: A Metaphysical Study. Open Court.
@

Chomsky, N.

(1967): Recent contributions to the theory of innate ideas. In: 'Synthese', vol. 17, pp.2-11.
@

Chomsky, N.

(1969): Linguistics and philosophy. In: S. Hook (Ed.): ' Language and Philosophy'. New York University Press.
@

Chomsky, N.

(1975): On cognitive capacity. In: 'Reflections on Language '.
@

Chomsky, N.

(1980): Rules and representations. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 3, pp.1-61.
@

Chomsky, N.

(1980): Discussion of Putnam's comments. In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): 'Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky'. Harvard University Press.
@

Chomsky, N.

(2003): Internalist explorations. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): ' Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Chomsky, N.; Fodor, J. A.

(1980): The inductivist fallacy. In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): 'Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky'. Harvard University Press.
@

Chrisley, R. L.

(1994): Taking embodiment seriously: Nonconceptual content and robotics . In: K. M. Ford; C. Glymour; P. Hayes (Ed.): 'Android Epistemology'. MIT Press.
@

Chrisley, R. L.

(1994): Why everything doesn't realize every computation. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.403-20.
@

Chrisley, R. L.

(1994): Taking embodiment seriously: Nonconceptual content and robotics . In: K. M. Ford; C. Glymour; P. Hayes (Ed.): 'Android Epistemology'. MIT Press.
@

Christensen, D.

(1992): Causal powers and conceptual connections. In: ' Analysis', vol. 52, pp.163-8.
@

Christensen, W. D.; Hooker C. A.

(2004): Representation and the meaning of life. In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind'. Elsevier.
@

Christiansen, M. H.; Chater, N.

(1994): Generalization and connectionist language learning . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.273-87.
@

Chung, M.; Fulford, K.; Graham, G.

(2005): The Philosophical Understanding of Schizophrenia . Oxford University Press.
@

Church, J.

(2003): Depression, depth, and the imagination. In: J. Philips; J. Morley (Ed.): 'Imagination and its Pathologies'. MIT Press.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1979): Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge University Press.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1981): Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 78, pp.67-90.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1982): Is `thinker' a natural kind?. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 21, pp.223-38.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1984): Matter and Consciousness. MIT Press.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1985): On the speculative nature of our self-conception. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 11, pp.157-173.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1986): Some reductive strategies in cognitive neurobiology. In: 'Mind', vol. 95, pp.279-309.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1988): Folk psychology and the explanation of human behavior. In: 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 62, pp.209-21.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1988): Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality: A reply to Jerry Fodor. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 55, pp.167-87.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1989): A Neurocomputational Perspective: The Nature of Mind and the Structure of Science. MIT Press.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1989): On the nature of theories: A neurocomputational perspective . In: 'Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 14.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1989): On the nature of explanation: A PDP approach. In: 'A Neurocomputational Perspective'.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1993): Theory, taxonomy, and methodology: A reply to Haldane's "Understanding folk". In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 67, pp.313-19.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1993): Evaluating our self-conception. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 8, pp.211-22.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1995): The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain. MIT Press.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1998): Conceptual similarity across sensory and neural diversity: The Fodor/Lepore challenge answered. In: ' Journal Of Philosophy', vol. 95, pp.5-32.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(1998): Conceptual similarity across sensory and neural diversity: The Fodor/Lepore challenge answered. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 95, pp.5-32.
@

Churchland, P. M.

(2005): Functionalism at forty: A critical retrospective. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 102, pp.33-50.
@

Churchland, P. M.; Churchland, P. S.

(1983): Stalking the wild epistemic engine. In: 'Nous', vol. 17, pp.5-20.
@

Churchland, P. M.; Churchland, P. S.

(1983): Stalking the wild epistemic engine. In: 'Nous', vol. 17, pp.5-18.
@

Churchland, P. M.; Churchland, P. S.

(1990): Could a machine think?. In: ' Scientific American', vol. 262, no.1, pp.32-37.
@

Churchland, P. M.; Churchland, P. S.

(1997): Recent work on consciousness: Philosophical, theoretical, and empirical. In: 'Seminars in Neurology ', vol. 17, pp.179-86.
@

Churchland, P. S.

(1978): Fodor on language learning. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 38, pp.149-59.
@

Churchland, P. S.

(1980): Language, thought, and information processing. In: 'Nous', vol. 14, pp.147-70.
@

Churchland, P. S.

(1980): A perspective on mind-brain research. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 77, pp.185-207.
@

Churchland, P. S.

(1981): Is determinism self-refuting?. In: 'Mind ', vol. 90, pp.99-101.
@

Churchland, P. S.

(1982): Mind-brain reduction: New light from philosophy of science . In: 'Neuroscience', vol. 7, pp.1041-7.
@

Churchland, P. S.

(1986): Neurophilosophy: Toward A Unified Science of the Mind-Brain . MIT Press.
@

Churchland, P. S.

(1987): Epistemology in the age of neuroscience. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 84, pp.546-53.
@

Churchland, P. S.

(2002): Brain-Wise: Studies in Neurophilosophy. MIT Press.
@

Churchland, P. S.; Sejnowski, T.

(1989): Neural representation and neural computation . In: L. Nadel (Ed.): 'Neural Connections, Mental Computations'. MIT Press.
@

Clapin, H.

(1991): Connectionism isn't magic. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp.167-84.
@

Clapin, H.

(1997): Problems with principle P. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 78, pp.261-77.
@

Clapin, H.

(2002): Philosophy and Mental Representation. Oxford University Press.
@

Clapin, H.

(2002): Tacit representation in functional architecture. In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Mental Representation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Clapin, H.

(2004): Representation in Mind: New Approaches to Mental Representation. Elsevier.
@

Clapp, L.

(2001): Disjunctive properties: multiple realizations. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 98, pp.111-136.
@

Clark, A.

(1980): Psychological Models and Neural Mechanisms: An Examination of Reductionism in Psychology. Oxford University Press.
@

Clark, A.

(1986): Psychofunctionalism and chauvinism. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 53, pp.535-59.
@

Clark, A.

(1986): A biological metaphor. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 1, pp.45-64.
@

Clark, A.

(1987): The kludge in the machine. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 2, pp.277-300.
@

Clark, A.

(1987): From folk psychology to naive psychology. In: ' Cognitive Science', vol. 11, pp.139-54.
@

Clark, A.

(1987): Being there: Why implementation matters to cognitive science. In: 'AI Review', vol. 1, pp.231-44.
@

Clark, A.

(1988): Thoughts, sentences and cognitive science. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 1, pp.263-78.
@

Clark, A.

(1989): Connectionism, nonconceptual content, and representational redescription.
@

Clark, A.

(1989): Beyond eliminativism. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 4, pp.251-79.
@

Clark, A.

(1989): Microcognition. MIT Press.
@

Clark, A.

(1990): Belief, opinion and consciousness. In: '1990'.
@

Clark, A.

(1990): Connectionist minds. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 90, pp.83-102.
@

Clark, A.

(1990): Connectionism, competence and explanation. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 41, pp.195-222.
@

Clark, A.

(1991): Radical ascent. In: 'Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 65, pp.211-27.
@

Clark, A.

(1991): In defense of explicit rules. In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Clark, A.

(1993): Mice, shrews, and misrepresentation. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 90, pp.290-310.
@

Clark, A.

(1993): Associative Engines: Connectionism, Concepts, and Representational Change . MIT Press.
@

Clark, A.

(1993): Superpositional connectionism: A reply to Marinov. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 3, pp.271-81.
@

Clark, A.

(1994): Beliefs and desires incorporated. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 91, pp.404-25.
@

Clark, A.

(1994): Representational trajectories in connectionist learning. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.317-32.
@

Clark, A.

(1995): Moving minds: Situating content in the service of real-time success . In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.89-104.
@

Clark, A.

(1995): Moving minds: Situating content in the service of real-time success . In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.89-104.
@

Clark, A.

(1996): Dealing in futures: Folk psychology and the role of representations in cognitive science. In: R. McCauley (Ed.): 'The Churchlands and their Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Clark, A.

(1996): True theories, false colors. In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement', vol. 63, pp.143-50.
@

Clark, A.

(1997): Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. MIT Press.
@

Clark, A.

(1997): Embodiment and the philosophy of mind. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Clark, A.

(1998): Time and mind. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 95, pp.354-76.
@

Clark, A.

(2001): Reasons, robots and the extended mind. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 16.
@

Clark, A.

(2001): Reasons, robots and the extended mind. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 16.
@

Clark, A.

(2002): The roots of 'norm-hungriness'. In (H. Clapin, ed) Philosophy and Mental Representation. Oxford University Press. Clark, A. 2002. Minds, brains, and tools . In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Mental Representation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Clark, A.

(2002): Artificial intelligence. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Clark, A.

(2003): Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies and the Future of Human Intelligence. Oxford University Press.
@

Clark, A.

(2003): Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence. Oxford University Press. Clark, A. 2004. Embodiment and the philosophy of mind . In: A. Peruzzi (Ed.): 'Mind and Causality'. John Benjamins.
@

Clark, A.

(2005): Intrinsic content, active memory, and the extended mind. In: 'Analysis', vol. 65, pp.1-11.
@

Clark, A. and Toribio, J.

(1994): Doing without representing. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 101, pp.401-31.
@

Clark, A.; Chalmers, D. J.

(1998): The extended mind. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 58, pp.7-19.
@

Clark, A.; Chalmers, D. J.

(1998): The extended mind. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 58, pp.7-19.
@

Clark, A.; Karmiloff-Smith, A.

(1994): The cognizer's innards: A psychological and philosophical perspective on the development of thought. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 8, pp.487-519.
@

Clark, A.; Thornton, S.

(1997): Trading spaces: Computation, representation, and the limits of uninformed learning. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 20, pp.57-66.
@

Clark, S. R. L.

(1987): The description and evaluation of animal emotion. In: C. Blakemore; S. Greenfield (Ed.): 'Mindwaves'. Blackwell.
@

Clark, S. R. L.

(1991): How many selves make me?. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 29, pp.213-33.
@

Clark, S. R. L.

(1996): Minds, memes, and multiples. In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 3, pp.21-28.
@

Clark, T.

(1992): The Turing test as a novel form of hermeneutics. In: ' International Studies in Philosophy', vol. 24, pp.17-31.
@

Clarke, J.

(1971): Mental structure and the identity theory. In: 'Mind ', vol. 80, pp.521-30.
@

Clarke, J.

(1972): Turing machines and the mind-body problem. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 23, pp.1-12.
@

Clarke, M.

(1996): Darwinian algorithms and indexical representation. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 63, pp.27-48.
@

Clarke, R.

(1992): Free will and the conditions of moral responsibility. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 66, pp.53-72.
@

Clarke, R.

(1993): Toward a credible agent-causal account of free will. In: 'Nous', vol. 27, pp.191-203.
@

Clarke, R.

(1996): Agent causation and event causation in the production of free action . In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 24, pp.19-48.
@

Clarke, R.

(1997): On the possibility of rational free action. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 88, pp.37-57.
@

Clarke, R.

(1999): Nonreductive physicalism and the causal powers of the mental. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 51, pp.295-322.
@

Clarke, R.

(2000): Modest libertarianism. In: 'Philosopical Perspectives ', vol. 14, pp.21-46.
@

Clarke, R.

(2002): Libertarian views: Critical survey of noncausal and event-causal accounts of free agency. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Clarke, R.

(2002): Free will. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Clarke, R.

(2002): Libertarian views: Noncausal and event-causal sccounts of free agency . In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Clayton, P.

(2004): Mind and Emergence: From Quantum to Consciousness. Oxford University Press.
@

Cleeremans, A.; French, R. M.

(1996): From chicken squawking to cognition: Levels of description and the computational approach in psychology. In: 'Psychologica Belgica', vol. 36, pp.5-29.
@

Cleland, C.

(1993): Is the Church-Turing thesis true?. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 3, pp.283-312.
@

Cleland, C. E.

(1995): Effective procedures and computable functions. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.9-23.
@

Cleve, van, J.

(1990): Supervenience and closure. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 58, pp.225-38.
@

Cleve, van, J.

(1990): Mind -- dust or magic? Panpsychism versus emergence. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 4, pp.215-226.
@

Cliff, D.

(1990): Computational neuroethology: A provisional manifesto.
@

Cling, A.

(1989): Eliminative materialism and self-referential inconsistency. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 56, pp.53-75.
@

Cling, A.

(1990): Disappearance and knowledge. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 57, pp.226-47.
@

Cling, A.

(1991): The empirical virtues of belief. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.303-23.
@

Coates, P.

(1995): Kripke's skeptical paradox: Normativeness and meaning. In: 'Mind', vol. 1986, pp.77-80.
@

Coates, P.

(1997): Meaning, mistake, and miscalculation. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 7, pp.171-97.
@

Coburn, R.

(1963): Shaffer on the identity of mental states and brain processes. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 60, pp.89-92.
@

Coburn, R. C.

(1963): Shaffer on the identity of mental states and brain processes. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 60.
@

Cockburn, D.

(1991): Human Beings. Cambridge University Press.
@

Cockburn, D.

(1994): Human beings and giant squids (on ascribing human sensations and emotions to non-human creatures). In: ' Philosophy', vol. 69, pp.135-50.
@

Coder, D.

(1969): Godel's theorem and mechanism. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 44, pp.234-7.
@

Coder, D.

(1973): The fundamental error of central-state materialism. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 10, pp.289-98.
@

Cohen, B.

(1995): Patterns lost: Indeterminism and Dennett's realism about beliefs. In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 76, pp.17-31.
@

Cohen, J.

(2003): Color: A functionalist approach. Philosophical Studies 113:1-42. Cohen, J. 2003. On the structural properties of the colors . In: 'Australian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 81, pp.78-95.
@

Cohen, L. J.

(1955): Can there be artificial minds?. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 16, pp.36-41.
@

Cohen, L. J.

(1979): On the psychology of prediction: Whose is the fallacy?. In: 'Cognition', vol. 7, pp.385-407.
@

Cohen, L. J.

(1980): Whose is the fallacy? A rejoinder to Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky . In: 'Cognition', vol. 8, pp.89-92.
@

Cohen, L. J.

(1981): Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated?. In: '1981'.
@

Cohen, L. J.

(1986): What sorts of machines can understand the symbols they use?. In: 'Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 60, pp.81-96.
@

Cohen, L. J.

(1986): The Dialogue of Reason. Cambridge University Press.
@

Cohen, L. J.

(1996): Does belief exist?. In: A. Clark; P. Millican (Ed.): ' Connectionism, Concepts, and Folk Psychology'. Oxford University Press.
@

Cole, D. J.

(1984): Thought and thought experiments. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 45, pp.431-44.
@

Cole, D. J.

(1991): Artificial intelligence and personal identity. In: ' Synthese', vol. 88, pp.399-417.
@

Cole, D. J.

(1991): Artificial minds: Cam on Searle. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 69, pp.329-33.
@

Cole, D. J.

(1994): The causal powers of CPUs. In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): ' Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons'. Academic Press.
@

Coleman, S.

(2000): Thought experiments and personal identity. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 98, pp.51-66.
@

Coles, L. S.

(1993): Engineering machine consciousness. In: 'AI Expert ', vol. 8, pp.34-41.
@

Collins, A.

(1992): On the paradox Kripke finds in Wittgenstein. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 18.
@

Collins, A. W.

(1997): Personal identity and the coherence of q-memory. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 47, pp.73-80.
@

Collins, D.

(1988): Belief, desire, and revision. In: 'Mind ', vol. 97, pp.333-42.
@

Collins, J.

(2000): Theory of mind, logical form and eliminativism. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.465-490.
@

Collins, J.

(2003): Cowie on the poverty of stimulus. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 136, pp.159-190.
@

Collins, J.

(2005): Faculty disputes. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 19, pp.503-33.
@

Collins, J.

(2005): On the input problem for massive modularity. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 15, pp.1-22.
@

Coltheart, M.; Davies, M.

(2000): Pathologies of Belief. Blackwell.
@

Combes, R.

(1988): Ockhamite reductionism. In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 28, pp.325-36.
@

Conee, E.

(1984): A defense of pain. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 46, pp.239-48.
@

Cook, K. S.; Levi, M.

(1990): The Limits of Rationality. University of Chicago Press.
@

Cooper, W. E.

(1980): Materialism and madness. In: 'Philosophical Papers ', vol. 9, pp.36-40.
@

Copeland, B. J.

(1993): The curious case of the Chinese gym. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 95, pp.173-86.
@

Copeland, B. J.

(1996): What is computation?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 108, pp.335-59.
@

Copeland, B. J.

(2000): The Turing test. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 10, pp.519-539.
@

Copeland, B. J.

(2000): Narrow versus wide mechanism: Including a re-examination of Turing's views on the mind-machine issue. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 97, pp.5-33.
@

Copeland, B. J.

(2003): The Chinese room from a logical point of view. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Copeland, J.

(2002): Narrow versus wide mechanism. In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): ' Computationalism: New Directions'. MIT Press.
@

Corazza, E.

(1994): Perspectival thoughts and psychological generalizations. In: 'Dialectica', vol. 48, pp.307-36.
@

Corazza, E.

(2004): Reflecting the Mind: Indexicality and Quasi-Indexicality. Oxford University Press.
@

Corbi, J. E.

(1993): Classical and connectionist models: Levels of description. In: 'Synthese', vol. 95, pp.141-68.
@

Cornman, J.

(1962): The identity of mind and body. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 59, pp.486-92.
@

Cornman, J.

(1968): On the elimination of `sensations' and sensations. In: ' Review of Metaphysics', vol. 22, pp.15-35.
@

Cosmides, L.; Tooby, J.

(1987): From evolution to behavior: Evolutionary psychology as the missing link. In: J. Dupre (Ed.): ' The Latest on the Best: Essays on Evolution and Optimality'. MIT Press.
@

Cosmides, L.; Tooby, J.

(1994): Beyond intuition and instinct blindness: Toward an evolutionary rigorous cognitive science. In: ' Cognition', vol. 50, pp.41-77.
@

Cotterill, R.

(2003): Cyberchild: A Simulation test-bed for consciousness studies. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 10.
@

Coulter, J.

(1995): The informed neuron: Issues in the use of information theory in the behavioral sciences. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.583-96.
@

Coulter, J.; Sharrock, S.

(2003): The hinterland of the Chinese room. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Cover, J.; Hawthorne, J.

(1996): Free agency and materialism. In: D. Howard-Snyder; J. Jordan (Ed.): 'Faith, Freedom, and Rationality'. Rowman and Littlefield.
@

Cowan, J.

(1968): Pleasure and Pain: A Study in Philosophical Psychology. Macmillan.
@

Cowie, F.

(1997): The logical problem of language acquisition. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 111, pp.17-51.
@

Cowie, F.

(1998): What's Within?. Oxford University Press.
@

Cowie, F.

(1998): Mad dog nativism. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 49, pp.227-252.
@

Cowie, F.

(2001): On cussing in church: in defense of What's Within?. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 16, pp.231-245.
@

Cowley, F.

(1971): The identity of a person and his body. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 68, pp.678-683.
@

Cozzo, C.

(2002): Does epistemological holism lead to meaning holism?. In: ' Topoi', vol. 21, pp.25-45.
@

Craig, E.

(1997): Meaning and privacy. In: B. Hale; C. Wright (Ed.): ' A Companion to the Philosophy of Language'. Blackwell.
@

Cram, H-R.

(1992): Fodor's causal theory of representation. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 42, pp.56-70.
@

Crane, T.

(1990): The language of thought: No syntax without semantics. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 5, pp.187-213.
@

Crane, T.

(1990): On an alleged analogy between numbers and propositions. In: 'Analysis', vol. 50, pp.224-30.
@

Crane, T.

(1991): All the difference in the world. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 41, pp.1-25.
@

Crane, T.

(1991): Why indeed? Papineau on supervenience. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 51, pp.32-7.
@

Crane, T.

(1991): All God has to do. In: 'Analysis', vol. 51, pp.235-44.
@

Crane, T.

(1992): Mental causation and mental reality. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 66, pp.185-202.
@

Crane, T.

(1993): A definition of physicalism: Reply to Pettit. In: ' Analysis', vol. 53, pp.224-27.
@

Crane, T.

(1995): The mental causation debate (Mental causation I). In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 69, pp.211-36.
@

Crane, T.

(1998): Intentionality as the mark of the mental. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Crane, T.

(2001): Intentional objects. In: 'Ratio', vol. 14, pp.298-317.
@

Crane, T.

(2001): The significance of emergence. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Crane, T.

(2001): Jacob on mental causation. In: 'Acta Analytica ', vol. 16, pp.15-21.
@

Crane, T.

(2001): Elements of Mind: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press.
@

Crane, T.

(2003): Mental substances. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Minds and Persons '. Cambridge University Press.
@

Crane, T.

(2003): The Mechanical Mind: A Philosophical Introduction to Minds, Machines, and Mental Representation. Routledge.
@

Crane, T.; Mellor, D. H.

(1990): There is no question of physicalism. In: ' Mind', vol. 99, pp.185-206.
@

Craver, C. F.

(2002): Interlevel experiments and multilevel mechanisms in the neuroscience of memory. In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplemental Volume', vol. 69.
@

Craver, C. F.

(2003): The making of a memory mechanism. In: ' Journal of the History of Biology', vol. 36, pp.153-95.
@

Craver, C. F; Darden, L.

(2001): Discovering mechanisms in neurobiology: The case of spatial memory. In (P. K. Machamer, R. Grush, and P. In: '2001'.
@

Crawford, C.

(1994): Notes on the Turing test. In: ' Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery', vol. 37, pp.13-15.
@

Crimmins, M.

(1992): Tacitness and virtual beliefs. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 7, pp.240-63.
@

Crimmins, M.

(2002): Talk about Beliefs. MIT Press.
@

Crisp, R.

(1996): Evolution and psychological unity. In: M. Bekoff; D. Jamieson (Ed.): 'Readings in Animal Cognition'. MIT Press.
@

Crisp, T.; Warfield, T.

(2000): The irrelevance of indeterministic counterexamples to principle beta. In: ' Philosophy & Phenomenological Research', vol. 61, pp.173-185.
@

Crittenden, C.

(1971): Ontology and mind-body identity. In: ' Philosophical Forum', vol. 2, pp.251-70.
@

Crockett, L.

(1994): The Turing Test and the Frame Problem: AI's Mistaken Understanding of Intelligence. Ablex.
@

Crook, S.

(2001): Why physics alone cannot define the 'physical': Materialism, metaphysics, and the formulation of physicalism. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 31, pp.333-360.
@

Crooks, M.

(2002): Intertheoretic identification and mind-brain reductionism. In: 'Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 23, pp.193-222.
@

Cruse, H.

(2001): The explanatory power and limits of simulation models in the neurosciences . In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences'. University of Pittsburgh Press.
@

Cruz, J. L. H.

(1998): Mindreading: Mental state ascription and cognitive architecture . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.323-340.
@

Cummins, D. D.

(1996): Evidence for the innateness of deontic reasoning. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 11, pp.160-90.
@

Cummins, D. D.; Cummins, R.

(1999): Biological preparedness and evolutionary explanation . In: 'Cognition', vol. 73.
@

Cummins, R.

(1975): Functional analysis. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp.741-64.
@

Cummins, R.

(1977): Programs in the explanation of behavior. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 44, pp.269-87.
@

Cummins, R.

(1981): What can be learned from Brainstorms?. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 12, pp.83-92.
@

Cummins, R.

(1982): The internal manual model of psychological explanation. In: 'Cognition and Brain Theory', vol. 5, pp.257-68.
@

Cummins, R.

(1983): The Nature of Psychological Explanation. MIT Press.
@

Cummins, R.

(1986): Inexplicit information. In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): ' The Representation of Knowledge and Belief'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Cummins, R.

(1989): Representation and covariation. In: S. Silvers (Ed.): ' ReRepresentation'. Kluwer.
@

Cummins, R.

(1989): Meaning and Mental Representation. MIT Press.
@

Cummins, R.

(1991): Methodological reflections on belief. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): ' Mind and Common Sense'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Cummins, R.

(1991): Mental meaning in psychological explanation. In: B. McLaughlin (Ed.): 'Dretske and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Cummins, R.

(1991): Form, interpretation, and the uniqueness of content: A response to Morris. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 1, pp.31-42.
@

Cummins, R.

(1991): The role of representation in connectionist explanation of cognitive capacities. In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Cummins, R.

(1992): Conceptual role semantics and the explanatory role of content. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 65, pp.103-127.
@

Cummins, R.

(1995): Connectionist and the rationale constraint on cognitive explanations . In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.105-25.
@

Cummins, R.

(1996): Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. MIT Press.
@

Cummins, R.

(1996): Why there is no symbol grounding problem?. In: ' Representations, Targets, and Attitudes'.
@

Cummins, R.

(1996): Systematicity. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 93, pp.591-614.
@

Cummins, R.

(1997): The LOT of the causal theory of mental content. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 94, pp.535-542.
@

Cummins, R.

(2002): Haugeland on representation and intentionality. In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Mental Representation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Cummins, R.; Poirier, P.

(2004): Representation and indication. In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind'. Elsevier.
@

Cummins, R.; Schwarz, G.

(1987): Radical connectionism. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 26, pp.43-61.
@

Cummins, R.; Schwarz, G.

(1991): Connectionism, computation, and cognition. In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Cunningham, S.

(2000): What Is a Mind?: An Integrative Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Hackett.
@

Curley, E. M.

(1975): Dreaming and conceptual revision. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 53, pp.119-41.
@

Currie, G.

(1984): Individualism and global supervenience. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 35, pp.345-58.
@

Currie, G.

(1995): Visual imagery as the simulation of vision. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 10, pp.25-44.
@

Currie, G.

(1995): Imagination as simulation: Aesthetics meets cognitive science. In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation'. Blackwell.
@

Currie, G.

(1996): Simulation-theory, theory-theory, and the evidence from autism. In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Currie, G.

(1998): Pretence, pretending, and metarepresenting. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.35-55.
@

Currie, G.

(2000): Imagination, delusion and hallucinations. In: M. Coltheart; M. Davies (Ed.): 'Pathologies of Belief'. Blackwell.
@

Currie, G.

(2002): Desire in imagination. In: T. Gendler; J. Hawthorne (Ed.): ' Conceivability and Possibility'. Oxford University Press.
@

Currie, G.

(2002): Imagination as motivation. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 102, pp.201-16.
@

Currie, G.; Jureidini, J.

(2001): Delusion, rationality, empathy. In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology', vol. 8, pp.159-62.
@

Currie, G.; Ravenscroft, I.

(1997): Mental simulation and motor imagery. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 64, pp.161-80.
@

Currie, G.; Ravenscroft, I.

(2002): Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford University Press.
@

Currie, G.; Ravenscroft, I.

(2002): Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford University Press.
@

Currie, G.; Sterelny, K.

(2000): How to think about the modularity of mind-reading. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 50, pp.145-160.
@

Curzer, H.

(1991): An ambiguity in Parfit's theory of personal identity. In: 'Ratio', vol. 4, pp.16-24.
@

Cussins, A.

(1990): The connectionist construction of concepts. In: M. Boden (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of AI'. Oxford University Press.
@

Cussins, A.

(1990): The connectionist construction of concepts. In: M. Boden (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of AI'. Oxford University Press.
@

Cussins, A.

(1992): Content, embodiment, and objectivity: The theory of cognitive trails . In: 'Mind', vol. 101, pp.651-88.

D


@

D'Aquili, E. G.; Newberg, A. B.

(1996): Consciousness and the machine. In: ' Zygon', vol. 31, pp.235-52.
@

D'Arms, J.; Jacobson, D.

(2000): The moralistic fallacy: On the "appropriateness" of emotions. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 61, pp.65-90.
@

Dainton, B.

(1996): Survival and experience. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 96, pp.17-36.
@

Dainton, B.

(2004): The self and the phenomenal. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 17, pp.365-89.
@

Dalenoort, G. J.

(1990): Toward a general theory of representation. In: ' Psychological Research', vol. 52, pp.229-237.
@

Dalrymple, H.

(1977): Some logical muddles in behaviorism. In: ' Southwestern Philosophical Studies', vol. 2, pp.64-72.
@

Daly, C.

(1995): Does physicalism need fixing?. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 55, pp.135-41.
@

Daly, C.

(1998): What are physical properties?. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 79, pp.196-217.
@

Damasio, A.

(1994): Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. Putnam.
@

Damasio, A.

(1999): The Feeling of what Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. Harcourt Brace and Co.
@

Dancy, J. (ed).

(1997): Reading Parfit. Blackwell.
@

Daniel, S. G.

(1999): Why even Kim-style psychophysical laws are impossible. In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 80, pp.225-237.
@

Danto, A.

(1960): On consciousness in machines. In: S. Hook (Ed.): ' Dimensions of Mind'. New York University Press.
@

Dartnall, T.

(2001): The pain problem. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp.95-102.
@

Dartnall, T.

(2005): Does the world leak into the mind? Active externalism, "internalism", and epistemology. In: ' Cognitive Science', vol. 29, pp.135-43.
@

Dascal, M.

(1992): Why does language matter to artificial intelligence?. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 2, pp.145-174.
@

Daugman, J. G.

(2001): Brain metaphor and brain theory. In: W. Bechtel; P. Mandik; J. Mundale; and R. Stufflebeam (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader'. Blackwell.
@

David, M.

(1997): Kim's functionalism. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp.133-48.
@

Davidson, D.

(1970): Mental events. In: L. Foster; J. Swanson (Ed.): ' Experience and Theory'. Humanities Press.
@

Davidson, D.

(1973): The material mind. In: P. Suppes (Ed.): ' Logic, Methodology and the Philosophy of Science'. North-Holland.
@

Davidson, D.

(1973): Freedom to act. In: T. Honderich (Ed.): ' Essays on Freedom of Action'. Routledge.
@

Davidson, D.

(1974): Psychology as philosophy. In: S. Brown (Ed.): ' Philosophy of Psychology'. Harper & Row.
@

Davidson, D.

(1980): Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford University Press.
@

Davidson, D.

(1982): Rational animals. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 36, pp.317-28.
@

Davidson, D.

(1984): First person authority. In: 'Dialectica', vol. 38.
@

Davidson, D.

(1985): Incoherence and irrationality. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 39, pp.345-54.
@

Davidson, D.

(1987): Knowing one's own mind. In: '1987'.
@

Davidson, D.

(1987): Problems in the explanation of action. In: P. Pettit; R. Sylvan; J. Norman (Ed.): 'Metaphysics and Morality'. Blackwell.
@

Davidson, D.

(1990): Turing's test. In: K. Said (Ed.): 'Modelling the Mind'. Oxford University Press.
@

Davidson, D.

(1992): The second person. In: 'Midwest Studies in Philosophy ', vol. 17.
@

Davidson, D.

(1992): Thinking causes. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): ' Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Davidson, D.

(1995): Laws and cause. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 49, pp.263-79.
@

Davidson, D.

(1995): Could there be a science of rationality?. In: ' International Journal of Philosophical Studies', vol. 3, pp.1-16.
@

Davidson, D.

(1999): The emergence of thought. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp.511-21.
@

Davies, D.

(1995): Dennett's stance on intentional realism. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 33, pp.299-312.
@

Davies, D.

(1995): Davidson, indeterminacy, and measurement. In: ' Acta Analytica', vol. 10, pp.37-56.
@

Davies, D.

(1998): On gauging attitudes. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 90, pp.129-54.
@

Davies, F.

(1998): How sceptical is Kripke's "sceptical solution". In: ' Philsophia', vol. 26, pp.119-40.
@

Davies, M.

(1986): Externality, psychological explanation, and narrow content. In: 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 60, pp.263-83.
@

Davies, M.

(1986): Tacit knowledge and the structure of thought and language. In: C. Travis (Ed.): 'Meaning and Interpretation'. Blackwell.
@

Davies, M.

(1989): Connectionism, modularity, and tacit knowledge. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 40, pp.541-55.
@

Davies, M.

(1989): Connectionism, modularity and tacit knowledge. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 40, pp.541-55.
@

Davies, M.

(1989): Tacit knowledge and subdoxastic states. In: A. George (Ed.): 'Reflections on Chomsky'. Blackwell.
@

Davies, M.

(1991): Individualism and perceptual content. In: 'Mind ', vol. 100, pp.461-84.
@

Davies, M.

(1991): Concepts, connectionism, and the language of thought. (W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & D. Rumelhart, eds) Philosophy and Connectionist Theory . In: '1991'.
@

Davies, M.

(1992): Aunty's own argument for the language of thought. In: J. Ezquerro; J. Larrazabal (Ed.): 'Cognition, Semantics and Philosophy'. Kluwer.
@

Davies, M.

(1992): The mental simulation debate. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): ' Truth and Rationality'. Ridgeview.
@

Davies, M.

(1995): Two notions of implicit rules. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.153-83.
@

Davies, M.

(1998): Externalism, architecturalism, and epistemic warrant. In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Davies, M.

(2000): Externalism and armchair knowledge. In: P. Boghossian; C. Peacocke (Ed.): 'New Essays on the A Priori'. Oxford University Press.
@

Davies, M.

(2003): Externalism, self-Knowledge and transmission of warrant. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Davies, M.

(2003): The problem of armchair knowledge. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): ' New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Davies, M.

(2004): Reference, contingency, and the two-dimensional framework. In: 'Philosophical Studies,', vol. 118, pp.83-131.
@

Davies, M.; Coltheart, M.; Langdon, R. and Breen, N.

(2001): Monothematic delusions: Towards a two-factor account. In: 'Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology ', vol. 8, pp.133-58.
@

Davies, M.; Davies, A. A.; Coltheart, M.

(2005): Anosognosia and the two-factor theory of delusions. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 20, pp.241-57.
@

Davies, M.; Humphreys, G.

(1993): Consciousness: Philosophical and Psychological Essays . Blackwell.
@

Davies, M.; Stone, T.

(1995): Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications. Blackwell.
@

Davies, M.; Stone, T.

(1995): Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate. Blackwell.
@

Davies, M.; Stone, T.

(2001): Mental simulation, tacit theory, and the threat of collapse . In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 29, pp.127-73.
@

Davies, P. S.

(1999): The conflict of evolutionary psychology. In: V. Hardcastle (Ed.): 'Where Biology Meets Psychology'. MIT Press.
@

Davies, S.

(1988): Kripke, Crusoe and Wittgenstein. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 66.
@

Davis, L.

(1997): Cerebral hemispheres. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 87, pp.207-22.
@

Davis, L. H.

(1998): Functionalism and personal identity. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 58, pp.781-804.
@

Davis, L. H.

(2001): Functionalism, the brain, and personal identity. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 102, pp.259-79.
@

Davis, S.

(2003): Arguments for externalism. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): ' Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Davis, W.

(1981): A theory of happiness. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 18, pp.111-20.
@

Davis, W.

(1986): Two senses of desire. In: J. Marks (Ed.): 'The Ways of Desire '. Precedent.
@

Davis, W. A.

(2005): Concept individuation, possession conditions, and propositional attitudes. In: 'Nous ', vol. 39, pp.140-66.
@

Daw, R.; Alter, T.

(2001): Free acts and robot cats. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 102, pp.345-57.
@

Dawkins, M. S.

(1987): Minding and mattering. In: C. Blakemore; S. Greenfield (Ed.): 'Mindwaves'. Blackwell.
@

Dawkins, M. S.

(1990): From an animal's point of view: Motivation, fitness, and animal welfare. In: '1990'.
@

Dawson, M. R. W.; Medler, D. A.; Berkeley, I. S. N.

(1997): PDP networks can provide models that are not mere implementations of classical theories. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 10, pp.25-40.
@

Dawson, M. R. W.; Schopflocher, D. P.

(1992): Autonomous processing in parallel distributed processing networks. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 5, pp.199-219.
@

De Anna, G.

(2002): The simple view of colour and the reference of perceptual terms. In: 'Philosophy', vol. 77, pp.87-108.
@

De Rosa, R.

(2000): On Fodor's claim that classical empiricists and rationalists agree on the innateness of ideas. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 14, pp.240-269.
@

DeLancey, C.

(1996): Emotion and the function of consciousness. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 3, pp.492-99.
@

DeLancey, C.

(1997): Emotion and the computational theory of mind. In: S. O'Nuillain; P. McKevitt; E. MacAogain (Ed.): 'Two Sciences of Mind'. John Benjamins.
@

DeLancey, C.

(1998): Real emotions. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp.467-487.
@

DeLancey, C.

(2001): Passionate Engines: What Emotions Reveal about the Mind and Artificial Intelligence. Oxford University Press.
@

DeWitt, R.

(1995): Vagueness, semantics, and the language of thought. In: ' Psyche', vol. 1.
@

Decety, J.

(2002): Neurophysiological evidence for simulation and action. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Dedrick, D.

(1995): Objectivism and the evolutionary value of color vision. In: 'Dialogue', vol. 34, pp.35-44.
@

Dedrick, D.

(1996): Can color be reduced to anything?. In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement', vol. 3, pp.134-42.
@

Degrazia, D.

(2002): Are we essentially persons? Olson, Baker, and a reply. In: 'Philosophical Forum', vol. 33, pp.81-99.
@

Deigh, J.

(1994): Cognitivism in the theory of emotions. In: 'Ethics ', vol. 104, pp.824-54.
@

Deigh, J.

(2004): Primitive emotions. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Demopoulos, W.

(1987): On some fundamental distinctions of computationalism. In: 'Synthese', vol. 70, pp.79-96.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1968): The nature of images and the introspective trap. In: 'Content and Consciousness'.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1971): Intentional systems. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 68, pp.87-106.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1975): Brain writing and mind reading. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 7, pp.403-15.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1976): Conditions of personhood.Lewis, D. 1976. In: A. Rorty (Ed.): 'The Identities of Persons'. University of California Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1976): Are dreams experiences?. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 73, pp.151-71.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1977): A cure for the common code. In: '1977'.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978): Brainstorms. MIT Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978): Where am I?. In: 'Brainstorms'.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978): On giving libertarians what they say they want. In: ' Brainstorms'.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978): The abilities of men and machines. In: 'Brainstorms '.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978): AI as philosophy and as psychology. In: M. Ringle (Ed.): 'Philosophical Perspectives on Artificial Intelligence'. Humanities Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978): Why you can't make a computer that feels pain. In: ' Synthese', vol. 38.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978): Two approaches to mental images. In: 'Brainstorms '.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1978): Current issues in the philosophy of mind. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 15, pp.249-261.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1981): Making sense of ourselves. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 12, pp.63-81.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1983): Beyond belief. In: A. Woodfield (Ed.): ' Thought and Object'. Oxford University Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1983): Beyond belief. In: A. Woodfield (Ed.): ' Thought and Object'. Oxford University Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1983): Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The `Panglossian paradigm' defended. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 6, pp.343-90.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1984): Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. MIT Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1984): Can machines think?. In: M. Shafto (Ed.): 'How We Know '. Harper & Row.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1984): Cognitive wheels: The frame problem of AI. In: Hookaway (Ed.): 'Minds, Machines and Evolution'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1985): Can machines think?. In: 'How We Know'.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1986): The logica l geography of computational approaches: A view from the east pole. In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): ' The Representation of Knowledge and Belief'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1987): The Intentional Stance. MIT Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1987): Fast thinking. In: 'The Intentional Stance'.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1988): Precis of The Intentional Stance. In: '1988'.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1988): Fear of Darwin's optimizing rationale.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1988): Evolution, error and intentionality. In: ' The Intentional Stance'.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1989): The origins of selves. In: 'Cogito ', vol. 3, pp.163-73.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1989): Cognitive ethology: Hunting for bargains or a wild goose chase? . In: Montefiore (Ed.): 'Goals, No-Goals and Own Goals'. Unwin Hyman.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1990): Granny's campaign for safe science. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1990): The interpretation of texts, people and other artifacts. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (Supplement)', vol. 50.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1991): Real patterns. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 88, pp.27-51.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1991): Ways of establishing harmony. In: B. McLaughlin (Ed.): ' Dretske and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1991): Mother Nature versus the walking encyclopedia. In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1991): Two contrasts: Folk craft vs folk science and belief vs opinion . In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): 'The Future of Folk Psychology'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1994): The practical requirements for making a conscious robot. In: 'Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A', vol. 349, pp.133-46.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1995): Cog: Steps toward consciousness in robots. In: T. Metzinger (Ed.): 'Conscious Experience'. Ferdinand Schoningh.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1995): Do animals have beliefs?. In: H. Roitblat; J. Meyer (Ed.): 'Comparative Approaches to Cognitive Science'. MIT Press.
@

Dennett, D. C.

(1996): Kinds of Minds. Basic Books.
@

DesAutels, P.

(1995): Two types of theories: The impact of Churchland's perceptual plasticity. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp.25-33.
@

Deutscher, M.

(1989): Remembering "Remembering". In: J. Heil (Ed.): ' Identity, Cause, and Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Devitt, M.

(1990): Meanings just ain't in the head. In: G. Boolos (Ed.): ' Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Devitt, M.

(1990): The narrow representational theory of mind. In: W. Lycan (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition'. Blackwell.
@

Devitt, M.

(1990): Transcendentalism about content. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 71, pp.247-63.
@

Devitt, M.

(1991): Why Fodor can't have it both ways. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Devitt, M.

(1994): The methodology of naturalistic semantics. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 91, pp.519-44.
@

Devitt, M.

(1994): A critique of the case for semantic holism. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 8, pp.281-306.
@

Devitt, M.

(1994): Semantic localism: Who needs a principled basis?. In: R. Casati; B. Smith; S. White (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences'. Holder-Pichler-Tempsky.
@

Devitt, M.

(2001): A shocking idea about meaning. In: ' Revue Internationale de Philosophie', vol. 55, pp.471-494.
@

Devitt, M.; Rey, G.

(1991): Transcending transcendentalism. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 72, pp.87-100.
@

Diamond, C.

(1989): Rules: Looking in the right place. In (D. Phillips & P. In: '1989'.
@

Dietrich, E.

(1988): Computers, intentionality, and the new dualism.
@

Dietrich, E.

(1989): Semantics and the computational paradigm in computational psychology . In: 'Synthese', vol. 79, pp.119-41.
@

Dietrich, E.

(1990): Computationalism. In: '1990'.
@

Dietrich, E.; Markman, A.

(2003): Discrete thoughts: Why cognition must use discrete representations. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp.95-119.
@

Dilman, I.

(1999): Free Will: An Historical and Philosophical Introduction. Routledge.
@

Dinsmore, J.

(1992): The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Divers, J.

(1996): Supervenience for operators. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 106, pp.103-12.
@

Dodwell, P.

(2000): Brave New Mind: A Thoughtful Inquiry into the Nature and Meaning of Mental Life. Oxford University Press.
@

Doepke, F.

(1990): The practical importance of personal identity. In: 'Logos ', vol. 83.
@

Dokic, J.

(2002): Reply to 'The scope and limit of mental simulation'. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Dokic, J.; Proust, J.

(2002): Simulation and Knowledge of Action. John Benjamins.
@

Dokic, Jerome,

(2001): Is memory purely preservative?. In: C. Hoerl; . T. McCormack (Ed.): 'Time and Memory'. Oxford University Press.
@

Donovan, C.

(1978): Eliminative materialism reconsidered. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 8.
@

Doppelt, G.

(1977): Incorrigibility, the mental, and materialism. In: '1977 '.
@

Dorschel, A.

(2002): The authority of the will. In: 'The Philosophical Forum ', vol. 33, pp.425-442.
@

Double, R.

(1981): Central state materialism. In: ' Philosophical Studies (Ireland)', vol. 28, pp.229-37.
@

Double, R.

(1983): Searle, programs and functionalism. In: ' Nature and System', vol. 5, pp.107-14.
@

Double, R.

(1987): The computational model of the mind and philosophical functionalism . In: 'Behaviorism', vol. 15, pp.131-39.
@

Double, R.

(1989): Puppeteers, hypnotists, and neurosurgeons. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 56, pp.163-73.
@

Double, R.

(1991): The Non-Reality of Free Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Double, R.

(1991): Determinism and the experience of freedom. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 72, pp.1-8.
@

Double, R.

(1992): How rational must free will be?. In: 'Metaphilosophy ', vol. 23, pp.268-78.
@

Double, R.

(1994): How to frame the free will problem. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 75, pp.149-72.
@

Double, R.

(1996): Metaphilosophy and Free Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Double, R.

(1997): Misdirection on the free will problem. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 34, pp.359-68.
@

Double, R.

(1999): In defense of the smart aleck: A reply to Ted Honderich. In: 'Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 24, pp.305-9.
@

Double, R.

(2002): Metaethics, metaphilosophy, and free will subjectivism. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Double, R.

(2002): Metaethics, metaphilosophy and free will subjectivism. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Double, R.

(2004): The ethical advantages of free will subjectivism. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 69.
@

Douglas, G.

(1998): Why pains are not mental objects. In: ' Philosophical Studies b', vol. 91, pp.127-148.
@

Downes, S.

(2002): Some recent developments in evolutionary approaches to the study of human cognition and behavior. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 16, pp.575-94.
@

Drai, D.

(2003): Externalism without identity. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 134, pp.463-75.
@

Dreckmann, F.

(1999): Animal beliefs and their contents. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp.597-615.
@

Dretske, F.

(1973): Perception and other minds. In: 'Nous ', vol. 7, pp.34-44.
@

Dretske, F.

(1981): Knowledge and the Flow of Information. MIT Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(1983): Precis of Knowledge and the Flow of Information. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 6, pp.55-90.
@

Dretske, F.

(1985): Machines and the mental. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 59, pp.23-33.
@

Dretske, F.

(1985): Machines and the mental. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 59, pp.23-33.
@

Dretske, F.

(1986): Misrepresentation. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): ' Belief: Form, Content, and Function'. Oxford University Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(1986): Aspects of cognitive representation. In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): 'The Representation of Knowledge and Belief'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(1987): The explanatory role of content. In: R. Grimm; D. Merrill (Ed.): 'Contents of Thought'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(1988): Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. MIT Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(1990): Putting information to work. In: P. Hanson (Ed.): ' Information, Language and Cognition'. University of British Columbia Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(1990): Does meaning matter?. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): ' Information, Semantics, and Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Dretske, F.

(1992): What isn't wrong with folk psychology. In: ' Metaphilosophy', vol. 23, pp.1-13.
@

Dretske, F.

(1993): The nature of thought. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 70, pp.185-99.
@

Dretske, F.

(1993): Mental events as structuring causes of behavior. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(1993): Can intelligence be artificial?. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 71, pp.201-16.
@

Dretske, F.

(1994): Reply to Slater and Garcia-Carpintero. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.203-8.
@

Dretske, F.

(1995): Reply: Causal relevance and explanatory exclusion. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Dretske, F.

(1996): The explanatory role of content: Reply to Melnyk and Noordhof. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 11, pp.223-29.
@

Dretske, F.

(2000): Perception, Knowledge and Belief: Selected Essays. Cambridge University Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(2001): Where is the mind?. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): ' Explaining Beliefs'. CSLI.
@

Dretske, F.

(2001): Norms, history, and the mental. In: D. Walsh (Ed.): ' Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(2003): Externalism and self-knowledge. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): ' New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(2003): Burge on mentalistic explanations, or why I am still epiphobic. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Dretske, F.

(2004): Psychological vs. biological explanations of behavior. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 32, pp.167-177.
@

Dreyfus, H. L.

(1972): What Computers Can't Do. Harper and Row.
@

Dreyfus, H. L.

(1979): A framework for misrepresenting knowledge. In: M. Ringle (Ed.): 'Philosophical Perspectives in Artificial Intelligence'. Humanities Press.
@

Dreyfus, H. L.

(1981): From micro-worlds to knowledge: AI at an impasse. In: J. Haugeland (Ed.): 'Mind Design'. MIT Press.
@

Dreyfus, H. L.; Dreyfus, S.

(1987): How to stop worrying about the frame problem even though it's computationally insoluble. In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma'. Ablex.
@

Dreyfus, H. L.; Dreyfus, S. E.

(1988): Making a mind versus modeling the brain: AI at a crossroads. In: '1988'.
@

Drozdek, A.

(2001): Descartes' Turing test. In: 'Epistemologia ', vol. 24, pp.5-29.
@

Duggan, T.; Gert, B.

(1979): Free will as the ability to will. In: 'Nous ', vol. 13, pp.197-217.
@

Duhrssen, A.

(1963): Philosophic alienation and the problem of other minds. In: '1963'.
@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(1977): Philosophical Essays on Dreaming. Cornell University Press.
@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(1978): Belief in dreams. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 56, pp.61-64.
@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(1978): Dreams, skepticism, and scientific research. In: ' Philosophia', vol. 8, pp.355-65.
@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(1990): Conceptual dependency as the language of thought. In: 'Synthese', vol. 82, pp.275-96.
@

Dunlop, C. E. M.

(2004): Mentalese semantics and the naturalized mind. In: ' Philosphical Psychology', vol. 17, pp.77-94.
@

Dupre, J.

(1988): Materialism, physicalism, and scientism. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 16, pp.31-56.
@

Dupre, J.

(1996): The solution to the problem of freedom of the will. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 10, pp.385-402.
@

Dupre, J.

(1996): The mental lives of nonhuman animals. In: M. Bekoff; D. Jamieson (Ed.): 'Readings in Animal Cognition'. MIT Press.
@

Dupuy, J.

(2000): The Mechanization of the Mind: On the Origins of Cognitive Science . Princeton University Press.
@

Dworkin, G.

(1970): Acting freely. In: 'Nous', vol. 4, pp.367-83.
@

Dworkin, G.

(1970): Determinism, Free Will, and Moral Responsibility. Prentice-Hall.
@

Dwyer, P.

(1989): Freedom and rule-following in Wittgenstein and Sartre. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 50, pp.49-68.
@

Dyer, M.

(1990): Intentionality and computationalism: minds, machines, Searle and Harnad . In: 'Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 2, pp.303-19.
@

Dyer, M.

(1990): Finding lost minds. In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 2, pp.329-39.
@

Dyer, M.

(1991): Connectionism versus symbolism in high-level cognition. In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind'. Kluwer.

E


@

Earle, W.

(1956): Memory. In: 'Review of Metaphysics', vol. 10, pp.3-27.
@

Ebbs, G.

(1996): Can we take our words at face value?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.499-530.
@

Ebbs, G.

(1997): Rule-Following and Realism. Harvard University Press.
@

Ebbs, G.

(2001): Is skepticism about self-knowledge coherent?. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 105, pp.43-58.
@

Ebbs, G.

(2003): A puzzle about doubt. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): ' New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Eccles, J.

(1976): Brain and free will. In: G. Globus (Ed.): ' Consciousness and the Brain'. Plenum Press.
@

Eckardt, von, B.

(1984): Cognitive psychology and principled skepticism. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 81, pp.67-88.
@

Eckardt, von, B.

(1993): What is Cognitive Science?. MIT Press.
@

Eckardt, von, B.

(1997): The empirical naivete in the current philosophical conception of folk psychology. In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind'. Pittsburgh University Press.
@

Eckardt, von, B.

(2003): The explanatory need for mental representations in cognitive science. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 3, no.18, pp.427-439..
@

Edis, T.

(1998): How Godel's theorem supports the possibility of machine intelligence . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 8, pp.251-262.
@

Edwards, J.

(1998): The simple theory of colour and the transparency of sense experience . In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Edwards, J.

(1999): Interpreted logical forms and knowing your own mind. In: 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 99, pp.169-90.
@

Edwards, J.

(2003): A reply to De Anna on the simple view of colour. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 78, pp.99-114.
@

Edwards, R.

(1975): Do pleasures and pains differ qualitatively?. In: ' Journal of Value Inquiry', vol. 9, pp.270-81.
@

Edwards, S.

(1994): Externalism in the Philosophy of Mind. Avebury.
@

Efron, A.

(1992): Residual asymmetric dualism: A theory of mind-body relations. In: 'Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 13, pp.113-36.
@

Egan, F.

(1991): Must psychology be individualistic?. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 100, pp.179-203.
@

Egan, F.

(1992): Individualism, computation, and perceptual content. In: ' Mind', vol. 101, pp.443-59.
@

Egan, F.

(1995): Computation and content. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 104, pp.181-203.
@

Egan, F.

(1995): Folk psychology and cognitive architecture. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 62, pp.179-96.
@

Egan, F.

(1996): Intentionality and the theory of vision. In: K. Akins (Ed.): ' Perception'. Oxford University Press.
@

Egan, F.

(1999): In defence of narrow mindedness. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 14, pp.177-94.
@

Egan, M. F.

(1989): What's wrong with the Syntactic Theory of Mind. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 56, pp.664-74.
@

Egan, M. F.

(1991): Propositional attitudes and the language of thought. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 21, pp.379-88.
@

Ehring, D.

(1987): Survival and trivial facts. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 47, pp.50-54.
@

Ehring, D.

(1995): Personal identity and the R-relation: Reconciliation through cohabitation . In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 73, pp.337-346.
@

Ehring, D.

(1996): Mental causation, determinables, and property instances. In: 'Nous', vol. 30, pp.461-80.
@

Ehring, D.

(1999): Fission, fusion, and the Parfit revolution. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 94, pp.329-32.
@

Ehring, D.

(2003): Part-whole physicalism and mental causation. In: ' Synthese', vol. 136, pp.359-388.
@

Eilan, N.

(2005): Joint attention, communication, and mind. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, eds) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds . In: '2005'.
@

Eilan, N.; Hoerl, C.; McCormack, T.; Roessler, J.

(2005): Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds. Oxford University Press.
@

Eklund, M.

(2002): Personal identity and conceptual incoherence. In: 'Nous ', vol. 36, pp.465-485.
@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(1998): Freedom, causation, and the consequence argument. In: 'Synthese', vol. 115, pp.333-54.
@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(1998): Protecting incompatibilist free action. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 35, pp.281-91.
@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(2000): Free Will: A Philosophical Study. Westview.
@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(2001): Agency and Responsibility: Essays on the Metaphysics of Freedom . Westview.
@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(2002): Libertarianism and Frankfurt-style cases. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Ekstrom, L. W.

(2003): Free will, chance, and mystery. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 22, pp.153-80.
@

Elder, C.

(1999): Physicalism and the fallacy of composition. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 50, pp.332-43.
@

Elder, C.

(2001): Mental causation versus physical causation: no contest. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 62, pp.110-127.
@

Elder, C.

(2001): Materialism and the mediated causation of behavior. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 103, pp.165-75.
@

Elder, C.

(2003): Kripkean externalism versus conceptual analysis. In: ' Facta Philosophica', vol. 5, pp.75-86.
@

Elder, C. L.

(1996): Content and the subtle extensionality of "... explains ...". In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 46, pp.320-32.
@

Elder, C. L.

(1998): What versus how in naturally selected representations. In: 'Mind', vol. 107, pp.349-363.
@

Eldridge, R.

(1986): The normal and the normative: Wittgenstein's legacy, Kripke, and Cavell . In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 46, pp.555-575.
@

Elgin, C.

(1980): Indeterminacy, underdetermination and the anomalous monism. In: 'Synthese', vol. 45, pp.233-55.
@

Eliasmith, C.

(1996): The third contender: A critical examination of the dynamicist theory of cognition. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 9, pp.441-63.
@

Eliasmith, C.

(1997): Computation and dynamical models of mind. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 7, pp.531-41.
@

Eliasmith, C.

(2003): Moving beyond metaphors: Understanding the mind for what it is . In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 100, pp.493-520.
@

Elliot, R.

(1991): Personal identity and the causal continuity requirement. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 41, pp.55-75.
@

Ellis, J.

(2005): Colour irrealism and the formation of colour concepts. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 83, pp.53-73.
@

Ellis, R.

(2000): Consciousness, self-organization, and the process-substratum relation: Rethinking nonreductive physicalism. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.173-190.
@

Ellis, R. D.

(2001): Can dynamical systems explain mental causation?. In: ' Journal of Mind And Behavior', vol. 22, pp.311-334.
@

Elster, J.

(2004): Emotion and action. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Elugardo, R.

(1981): Machine functionalism and the New Lilliputian argument. In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 62, pp.256-61.
@

Elugardo, R.

(1983): Machine realization and the New Lilliputian argument. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 43, pp.267-75.
@

Elugardo, R.

(1988): Against weak psychophysical supervenience. In: ' Dialectica', vol. 42, pp.129-43.
@

Elugardo, R.

(1993): Burge on content. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 53, pp.367-84.
@

Emmett, K.

(1978): Oneiric experiences. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 34, pp.445-50.
@

Enc, B.

(1983): In defense of the identity theory. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 80, pp.279-98.
@

Enc, B.

(1996): Nonreducible supervenient causation. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Endicott, R. P.

(1989): On physical multiple realization. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 70, pp.212-24.
@

Endicott, R. P.

(1991): Macdonald on type reduction via disjunction. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 29, pp.209-14.
@

Endicott, R. P.

(1993): Species-specific properties and more narrow reductive strategies . In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 38, pp.303-21.
@

Endicott, R. P.

(1996): Searle, syntax, and observer-relativity. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 26, pp.101-22.
@

Endicott, R. P.

(1998): Collapse of the new wave. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 95, pp.53-72.
@

Engel, M.

(1993): The problem of other minds: a reliable solution. In: ' Acta Analytica', vol. 11, pp.87-109.
@

Engel, P.

(1987): Functionalism, belief, and content. In: Torrance (Ed.): ' The Mind and the Machine'. Horwood.
@

Engel, P.

(2000): Wherein lies the normative dimension in meaning and mental content? . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 100, pp.305-321.
@

Engel, P.

(2002): Intentionality, normativity, and community. In: ' Facta Philosophica', vol. 4, pp.25-49.
@

Erion, G. J.

(2001): The Cartesian test for automatism. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.29-39.
@

Erneling, C.

(2004): The Mind as a Scientific Object: Between Brain and Culture. Oxford University Press.
@

Esfeld, M.

(1998): Holism and analytic philosophy. In: 'Mind ', vol. 107, pp.365-80.
@

Evans, D.

(2002): The search hypothesis of emotions. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 53, pp.497-509.
@

Evans, D.; Cruse, P.

(2004): Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality. Oxford University Press.
@

Evans, S.

(1981): Separable souls: A defense of minimal dualism. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 19.
@

Everett, T.

(2000): Other voices, other minds. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 78, pp.213-222.
@

Everitt, N.

(1981): A problem for the eliminative materialist. In: 'Mind ', vol. 90, pp.428-34.
@

Everitt, N.

(1983): How not to solve a problem for the eliminative materialist. In: 'Mind', vol. 92, pp.590-92.
@

Ewing, A. C.

(1953): Professor Ryle's attack on dualism. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 53, pp.47-78.

F


@

Falk, A.

(1981): On some modal confusions in compatibilism. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 18, pp.141-48.
@

Falk, A. E.

(2004): Desire and Belief: Introduction to Some Recent Philosophical Debates . Hamilton Books, University Press of America.
@

Falvey, K.

(1999): A natural history of belief. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 80, pp.324-345.
@

Falvey, K.

(1999): A natural history of belief. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 80, pp.324-345.
@

Falvey, K.

(2000): The compatibility of anti-individualism and privileged access. In: 'Analysis', vol. 60, pp.137-142.
@

Falvey, K.

(2000): The basis of first-person authority. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 28, pp.69-99.
@

Falvey, K.

(2003): Memory and knowledge of content. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): ' New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Falvey, K.; Owens, J.

(1994): Externalism, self-knowledge, and skepticism. In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 103, pp.107-37.
@

Farah, M. J.

(1988): Is visual imagery really visual: Some overlooked evidence from neuropsychology. In: ' Psychological Review', vol. 95, pp.307-17.
@

Farkas, K.

(2003): What is externalism?. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 112, pp.187-208.
@

Farrell, B.

(1950): Experience. In: 'Mind', vol. 59, pp.170-98.
@

Feest, U.

(2003): Functional analysis and the autonomy of psychology. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 70, pp.937-948.
@

Feferman, S.

(1996): Penrose's Godelian argument. In: 'Psyche ', vol. 2, pp.21-32.
@

Feigl, H.

(1958): The `mental' and the `physical'. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 2, pp.370-497.
@

Feigl, H.

(1959): Other minds and the egocentric predicament. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 56, pp.980-87.
@

Feigl, H.

(1971): Some crucial issues of mind-body monism. In: '1971'.
@

Feldman, R.

(1988): Rationality, reliability, and natural selection. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 55, pp.218-27.
@

Fellous, J.

(2004): Who Needs Emotions: The Brain meets the Robot. Oxford University Press.
@

Fellows, R.

(2000): Animal belief. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 75, pp.587-599.
@

Ferguson, S.

(2002): Methodology in evolutionary psychology. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 17, pp.635-50.
@

Fernandez, J.

(2003): Privileged access naturalized. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 53, pp.352-372.
@

Fernandez, J.

(2004): Externalism and self-knowledge: A puzzle in two dimensions. In: 'European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 12, pp.17-37.
@

Fernandez, J.

(2004): Externalism and self-knowledge: A puzzle in two dimensions. In: 'European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 12, pp.17-37.
@

Fernandez, J.

(2005): Privileged access revisited. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 55.
@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1990): The frame problem: Artificial intelligence meets David Hume. In: 'International Journal of Expert Systems', vol. 3, pp.219-232.
@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1990): Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits. Kluwer.
@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1990): Evolution, rationality and testability. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 82, pp.423-39.
@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1991): Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Paragon House.
@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1992): Connectionism and cognition: Why Fodor and Pylyshyn are wrong. In: A. Clark; R. Lutz (Ed.): 'Connectionism in Context'. Springer-Verlag.
@

Fetzer, J. H.

(1994): Mental algorithms: Are minds computational systems?. In: 'Pragmatics and Cognition', vol. 21, pp.1-29.
@

Feyerabend, P.

(1963): Mental events and the brain. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 40, pp.295-6.
@

Feyerabend, P.

(1963): Materialism and the mind-body problem. In: ' Review of Metaphysics', vol. 17, pp.49-67.
@

Ficsher, J. M.

(1983): Incompatibilism. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 43, pp.127-37.
@

Field, H.

(1977): Logic, meaning, and conceptual role. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 74, pp.379-409.
@

Field, H.

(1978): Mental representation. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 13, pp.9-18.
@

Field, H.

(1978): Mental representation. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 13, pp.9-61.
@

Field, H.

(1989): "Narrow" aspects of intentionality and the information-theoretic approach to content. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Fields, C.

(1984): Double on Searle's Chinese Room. In: 'Nature and System ', vol. 6, pp.51-54.
@

Fields, C.

(1994): Real machines and virtual intentionality: An experimentalist takes on the problem of representational content. In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): 'Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons'. Academic Press.
@

Fields, L.

(1987): Parfit on personal identity and desert. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 37, pp.432-41.
@

Finch, A.; Warfield, T.

(1998): The Mind argument and libertarianism. In: ' Mind', vol. 107, pp.515-28.
@

Fine, A.

(1993): Indeterminism and the freedom of the will. In: J. Earman (Ed.): 'Philosophical Problems of the Internal and External World'. University of Pittsburgh Press.
@

Fine, A.

(1996): Science as child's play: Tales from the crib. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 63, pp.534-37.
@

Finke, R. A.

(1989): Principles of Mental Imagery. MIT Press.
@

Finkelstein, D.

(1999): On self-blindness and inner sense. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 26, pp.105-19.
@

Finkelstein, D.

(2003): Expression and the Inner. Harvard University Press.
@

Finkelstein, D. H.

(2000): Wittgenstein on rules and Platonism. In: A. Crary; R. Read (Ed.): 'The New Wittgenstein'. Routledge.
@

Finn, D. R.

(1971): Putnam and logical behaviourism. In: 'Mind ', vol. 80, pp.432-36.
@

Fischer, J.

(1985): Functionalism and propositions. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 48, pp.295-311.
@

Fischer, J. M.

(1982): Responsibility and control. In: 'Journal of Philsophy ', vol. 79, pp.24-40.
@

Fischer, J. M.

(1994): The Metaphysics of Free Will: A Study of Control. Blackwell.
@

Fischer, J. M.

(1996): A new compatibilism. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp.49-66.
@

Fischer, J. M.

(2002): Frankfurt-type examples and semi-compatibilism. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Fischer, J. M.; Ravizza, M.

(1992): When the will is free. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 6, pp.423-51.
@

Fischer, J. M.; Ravizza, M.

(1996): Free will and the modal principle. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 3, pp.213-30.
@

Fischer, J. M.; Ravizza, M.

(1998): Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Cambridge University Press.
@

Fisher, C. M.

(2001): If there were no free will. In: 'Medical Hypotheses ', vol. 56, pp.364-366.
@

Fisher, J.

(1988): The wrong stuff: Chinese rooms and the nature of understanding. In: 'Philosophical Investigations', vol. 11, pp.279-99.
@

Flanagan, O.

(1994): Multiple identity, character transformation, and self-reclamation . In: G. Graham; G. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology'. MIT Press.
@

Flanagan, O.

(1995): Deconstructing dreams: The spandrels of sleep. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 92, pp.5-27.
@

Flanagan, O.

(1996): Self-expression in sleep: Neuroscience and dreams. In: 'Self-Expressions'.
@

Flanagan, O.

(2000): Dreaming Souls: Sleep, Dreams, and the Evolution of the Conscious Mind . Oxford University Press.
@

Flanagan, O. J.

(1984): The Science of the Mind. MIT Press.
@

Flanagan, O. J.

(1991): Consciousness. In: 'The Science of the Mind'.
@

Flanagan, O. J.; McCreadie-Albright, T.

(1974): Malcolm and the fallacy of behaviorism . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 26, pp.425-30.
@

Fletcher, G.

(1995): The Scientific Credibility of Folk Psychology. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Fletcher, G.

(1995): Two uses of folk psychology: Implications for psychological science . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 8, pp.375-88.
@

Flint, T.

(1987): Compatibilism and the argument from unavoidability. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 84, pp.423-40.
@

Floridi, L.

(2003): Two approaches to the philosophy of information. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 13, pp.459-469.
@

Fodor, J.

(1995): Concepts: A potboiler. Cognition 50:133-51. Also in (E. Villanueva, ed) Content. In: '1995'.
@

Fodor, J.

(1997): Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 11, pp.149-63.
@

Fodor, J.

(1998): Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford University Press.
@

Fodor, J.

(2000): The Mind Doesn't Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology. MIT Press.
@

Fodor, J.

(2000): In Critical Condition: Polemical Essays on Cognitive Science and the Philosophy of Mind. MIT Press.
@

Fodor, J.

(2001): Language, thought and compositionality. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 16, pp.1-15.
@

Fodor, J.

(2003): Hume Variations. Oxford University Press.
@

Fodor, J.

(2004): Having concepts: A brief refutation of the twentieth Century. Mind and Language 19:29-47. Franks, B. 1992. Realism and folk psychology in the ascription of concepts . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 5, pp.369-90.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1968): Materialism. In: 'Psychological Explanation'.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1968): Psychological Explanation. Random House.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1968): The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanation. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 65, pp.627-40.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1974): Special sciences. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 28, pp.97-115.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1975): The Language of Thought. Harvard University Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1975): Imagistic representation. In: 'The Language of Thought '.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1978): Propositional attitudes. In: 'Monist ', vol. 61, pp.501-23.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1978): Tom Swift and his procedural grandmother. In: ' Cognition', vol. 6, pp.229-47.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1978): Computation and reduction. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 9.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1980): Methodological solipsism as a research strategy in cognitive psychology . In: 'Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 3, pp.63-109.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1980): Reply to Putnam. In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): ' Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky'. Harvard University Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1980): On the impossibility of acquiring `more powerful' structures. In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): 'Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky'. Harvard University Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1981): Three cheers for propositional attitudes. In: ' Representations'.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1981): The present status of the innateness controversy. In: ' Representations'.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1982): Cognitive science and the twin-earth problem. In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic', vol. 23, pp.98-118.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1983): The Modularity of Mind. MIT Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1984): Semantics, Wisconsin style. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 59, pp.231-50.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1984): Observation reconsidered. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 51, pp.23-43.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1985): Precis of The modularity of mind. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 8, pp.1-42.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1986): Information and association. In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic', vol. 27.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1986): Banish DisContent. In: J. Butterfield (Ed.): ' Language, Mind, and Logic'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1986): Why paramecia don't have mental representations. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 10, pp.3-23.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1986): The modularity of mind. In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): ' Meaning and Cognitive Structure'. Ablex.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987): Why there still has to be a language of thought. In: ' Psychosemantics'.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987): Individualism and supervenience. In: 'Psychosemantics '.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987): A situated grandmother. In: '1987'.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987): Meaning and the world order. In: 'Psychosemantics'.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987): Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind . MIT Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1987): Modules, frames, fridgeons, sleeping dogs, and the music of the spheres . In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma'. Ablex.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1988): A reply to Churchland's `Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality'. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 55, pp.188-98.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1989): Why should the mind be modular?. In: A. George (Ed.): ' Reflections on Chomsky'. Blackwell.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1989): Making mind matter more. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 17, pp.59-79.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990): A theory of content II. In: 'A Theory of Content'.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990): Information and representation. In: P. Hanson (Ed.): ' Information, Language and Cognition'. University of British Columbia Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990): Psychosemantics, or, Where do truth conditions come from?. In: W. Lycan (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition'. Blackwell.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990): A theory of content I. In: 'A Theory of Content'.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1990): A Theory of Content and Other Essays. MIT Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1991): A modal argument for narrow content. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 88, pp.5-26.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1991): Yin and Yang in the Chinese Room. In: D. Rosenthal (Ed.): ' The Nature of Mind'. Oxford University Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1991): You can fool some of the people all of the time, everything else being equal: Hedged laws and psychological explanation . In: 'Mind', vol. 100, pp.19-34.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1994): The Elm and the Expert. MIT Press.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(1997): Connectionism and the problem of systematicity (continued): Why Smolensky's solution still doesn't work. In: 'Cognition', vol. 62, pp.109-19.
@

Fodor, J. A.

(2001): Doing without What's Within: Fiona Cowie's critique of nativism . In: 'Mind', vol. 110, pp.99-148.
@

Fodor, J. A.; Bever, T.; Garrett, M.

(1974): The specificity of language skills. In: 'The Psychology of Language'.
@

Fodor, J. A.; LePore, E.

(1991): Why meaning (probably) isn't conceptual role. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 6, pp.328-43.
@

Fodor, J. A.; LePore, E.

(1992): Holism: A Shopper's Guide. Blackwell.
@

Fodor, J. A.; LePore, E.

(1993): Is intentional ascription intrinsically normative?. In: B. Dahlbom (Ed.): 'Dennett and His Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Fodor, J. A.; LePore, E.

(1993): Precis of Holism: A Shopper's Guide. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 53, pp.637-682.
@

Fodor, J. A.; McLaughlin, B. P.

(1990): Connectionism and the problem of systematicity: Why Smolensky's solution doesn't work. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 35, pp.183-205.
@

Fodor, J. A.; Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1981): How direct is visual perception?: Some reflections on Gibson's `ecological approach'. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 9, pp.139-96.
@

Fodor, J. A.; Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1988): Connectionism and cognitive architecture. In: 'Cognition', vol. 28, pp.3-71.
@

Fodor, J.; Lepore, E.

(1996): The red herring and the pet fish: Why concepts still can't be prototypes. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 58, pp.253-70.
@

Fodor, J.; Lepore, E.

(2002): The Compositionality Papers. Oxford University Press.
@

Foley, R.

(1978): Compatibilism. In: 'Kind', vol. 87, pp.421-28.
@

Foley, R.

(1987): Dretske's `information-theoretic' account of knowledge. In: '1987'.
@

Fonseca, J.

(2004): On Bickle's failure to give a formal account of the location in the new-wave reductionist spectrum. In: 'Disputatio', vol. 17.
@

Foot, P.

(1957): Free will as involving determinism. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 66, pp.439-50.
@

Forbes, G.

(1983): Scepticism and semantic knowledge. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 84, pp.223-37.
@

Forbes, G.

(1987): A dichotomy sustained. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 51, pp.187-211.
@

Forrest, P.

(1985): Backwards causation in defense of free will. In: 'Mind ', vol. 94, pp.210-17.
@

Forrest, P.

(1988): Supervenience: The grand-property hypothesis. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 66, pp.1-12.
@

Forrest, P.

(1992): Universals and universalisability: An interpretation of Oddie's discussion of supervenience. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 70, pp.93-98.
@

Forster, M.; Saidel, E.

(1994): Connectionism and the fate of folk psychology. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.437-52.
@

Forster, M.; Shapiro, L.

(2000): Prediction and accommodation in evolutionary psychology . In: 'Psychological Inquiry', vol. 11, pp.31-33.
@

Foss, J.

(1994): On the evolution of intentionality as seen from the intentional stance . In: 'Inquiry', vol. 37, pp.287-310.
@

Foss, J.

(1995): Materialism, reduction, replacement, and the place of consciousness in science. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 92, pp.401-29.
@

Foss, J. E.

(1985): A materialist's misgivings about eliminative materialism. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 11, pp.105-33.
@

Foss, J. E.

(1992): Introduction to the epistemology of the brain: Indeterminacy, micro-specificity, chaos, and openness. In: 'Topoi', vol. 11, pp.45-57.
@

Foster, C.

(1990): Algorithms, abstraction and implementation. Academic Press.
@

Foster, D.

(2003): Does colour constancy exist?. In: ' Trends in Cognitive Science', vol. 7, pp.439-443.
@

Foster, J.

(1994): The token-identity thesis. In: R. Warner; T. Szubka (Ed.): ' The Mind-Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate'. Blackwell.
@

Foti, V. M.

(1990): The dimension of color. In: ' International Studies in Philosophy', vol. 22, pp.13-28.
@

Fowler, C.

(1996): A pragmatic defense of free will. In: ' Journal of Value Inquiry', vol. 30, pp.247-60.
@

Fraassen, van, B.

(2004): Transcendence of the ego (the nonexistent knight). In: 'Ratio', vol. 17, pp.453-77.
@

Francescotti, R.

(2000): Ontological physicalism and property pluralism: Why they are incompatible. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 81, pp.349-362.
@

Francescotti, R.

(2002): Understanding physical realization (and what it does not entail) . In: 'Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 23, pp.279-292.
@

Francescotti, R. M.

(1991): Externalism and the Marr theory of vision. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 42, pp.227-38.
@

Francescotti, R. M.

(1997): What multiple realizability does not show. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 18, pp.13-28.
@

Francescotti, R. M.

(1998): Defining "physicalism". In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 19, pp.51-64.
@

Francescotti, R. M.

(1998): The nonreductionist's troubles with supervenience. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 89, pp.105-24.
@

Frank, M. C.

(2004): Against informational atomism. In: 'The Dualist ', vol. 10.
@

Frank, R.

(1988): Passions Within Reason: The Strategic Role of Emotions. Norton.
@

Frankfurt, H.

(1969): Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 65, pp.829-39.
@

Frankfurt, H.

(1971): Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 68, pp.5-20.
@

Frankish, K.

(1998): A matter of opinion. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp.423-442.
@

Franklin, S.

(2003): A conscious artifact?. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 10.
@

Franks, B.

(1995): On explanation in cognitive science: Competence, idealization, and the failure of the classical cascade. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 46, pp.475-502.
@

Franks, B.

(2005): The role of "the environment" in cognitive and evolutionary psychology . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 18, pp.59-82.
@

Frapolli, M.; Romero, E.

(2003): Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind: Essays on Tyler Burge. CSLI.
@

Frapolli, M.; Romero, E.

(2003): Anti-individualism and basic self-knowledge. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Freeman, N. H.

(1995): Theories of mind in collision: Plausibility and authority. In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation'. Blackwell.
@

Freeman, W.

(1997): Nonlinear neurodynamics of intentionality. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 18, pp.291-304.
@

Freeman, W.; Skarda, C. A.

(1990): Representations: who needs them?. In: J. McGaugh; J. Weinberger; G. Lynch (Ed.): 'Brain Organization and Memory'. Guilford Press.
@

French, R. M.

(1990): Subcognition and the limits of the Turing test. In: ' Mind', vol. 99, pp.53-66.
@

French, R. M.

(1995): Refocusing the debate on the Turing Test: A response. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.59-60.
@

Fricker, E.

(1998): Self-knowledge: Special access vs. artefact of grammar -- A dichotomy rejected. In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Frijda, N.

(2002): Emotions and motivational states. In: ' European Review of Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.11-32.
@

Frijda, N. H.

(1986): The Emotions. Cambridge University Press.
@

Fuery, P.

(1995): Theories of Desire. Melbourne University Press.
@

Fulford, K. W. M.

(1994): Value, illness, and failure of action: Framework for a philosophical psychopathology of delusions. In: G. Graham; L. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology'. MIT Press.
@

Fulford, K. W. M.

(1995): Mind and madness: New directions in the philosophy of psychiatry . In: A. Griffiths (Ed.): 'Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychiatry'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Fuller, G.

(1995): Simulation and psychological concepts. In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation'. Blackwell.
@

Fumerton, R.

(2003): Introspection and internalism. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): ' New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Funkhouser, E.

(2003): Willing belief and the norm of truth. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 115, pp.179-95.
@

Furlong, E. J.

(1948): Memory. In: 'Mind', vol. 57, pp.16-44.
@

Furlong, E. J.

(1951): A Study in Memory: A Philosophical Essay. Nelson.
@

Furlong, E. J.

(1956): The empiricist theory of memory. In: 'Mind ', vol. 65, pp.542-47.
@

Furlong, F. W.

(1981): Determinism and free will: Review of the literature. In: 'American Journal of Psychiatry', vol. 138, pp.435-39.

G


@

Gaifman, H.

(2000): What Godel's incompleteness result does and does not show. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 97, pp.462-471.
@

Gaita, R.

(1992): Animal thoughts. In: 'Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 15, pp.227-44.
@

Gaito, J.

(1960): Description, explanation, and reductionism in psychology. In: 'Psychological Reports', vol. 6, pp.203-5.
@

Gaito, J.; Leonard, D.

(1965): Philosophical and empirical reductionism in psychology . In: 'Journal of General Psychology', vol. 72, pp.69-75.
@

Gallagher, K.

(1964): Intersubjective knowledge. In: '1964'.
@

Gallagher, S.

(2001): The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or primary interaction? . In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 8, pp.83-108.
@

Gallese, V.

(2001): The 'shared manifold' hypothesis: From mirror neurons to empathy . In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 8, pp.33-50.
@

Gallois, A.

(1977): Van Inwagen on free will and determinism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 32, pp.99-105.
@

Gallois, A.

(1994): Deflationary self-knowledge. In: M. Michael; J. O'Leary-Hawthorne (Ed.): 'Philosophy in Mind: The Place of Philosophy in the Study of Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Gallois, A.

(1996): The World Without, the Mind Within: An Essay on First-Person Authority . Cambridge University Press.
@

Gallois, A.; O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.

(1996): Externalism and skepticism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 81, pp.1-26.
@

Gampel, E. H.

(1997): The normativity of meaning. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 86, pp.221-42.
@

Ganeri, J.

(2000): Cross-modality and the self. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 61, pp.639-658.
@

Ganeri, J.

(2004): An irrealist theory of self. In: ' Harvard Review of Philosophy', vol. 12.
@

Garcia-Carpintero, M.

(1994): The supervenience of mental content. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 68, pp.117-135.
@

Garcia-Carpintero, M.

(1994): Dretske on the causal efficacy of meaning. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.181-202.
@

Garcia-Carpintero, M.

(1996): Two spurious varieties of compositionality. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 6, pp.159-72.
@

Gardenfors, P.

(1997): Meanings as conceptual structures. In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind'. Pittsburgh University Press.
@

Gardner, S.

(1994): Other minds and embodiment. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 94, pp.35-52.
@

Gardner, S.

(1996): Irrationality and the Philosophy of Psychoanalysis. Cambridge University Press.
@

Garfield, J.

(1987): Modularity in Knowledge Representation and Natural-Language Understanding. MIT Press.
@

Garfield, J.

(1988): Belief in Psychology: A Study in the Ontology of Mind. MIT Press.
@

Garfield, J.

(1997): Mentalese not spoken here: Computation, cognition, and causation . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 10, pp.413-35.
@

Garfield, J.

(2000): Thought as language: A metaphor too far. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 14, pp.85-101.
@

Garfield, J. L.

(2000): The meanings of "meaning" and "meaning": Dimensions of the sciences of mind. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 31, pp.421-440.
@

Garfield, J. L.

(2001): Pain deproblematized. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 14, pp.103-7.
@

Garnett, A. C.

(1942): Scientific method and the concept of emergence. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 39, pp.477-86.
@

Garnett, A. C.

(1965): Body and mind: the identity thesis. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 43, pp.77-81.
@

Garrett B.

(1990): Personal identity and extrinsicness. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 59, pp.177-194.
@

Garrett, B.

(1991): Personal identity and reductionism. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 51, pp.361-373.
@

Garrett, B.

(1992): Persons and values. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 42, pp.337-44.
@

Garrett, B. J.

(1998): Pluralism, causation, and overdetermination. In: ' Synthese', vol. 116, pp.355-78.
@

Garrett, B. J.

(1999): Davidson on causal relevance. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 12, pp.14-33.
@

Garson, J.

(2003): Simulation and connectionism: What is the connection?. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 16, pp.499-515.
@

Garson, J.

(2003): The introduction of information into neurobiology. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 70, pp.926-936.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1991): What connectionists cannot do: The threat to Classical AI. In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1993): Mice in mirrored mazes and the mind. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 6, pp.123-34.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1994): No representations without rules: The prospects for a compromise between paradigms in cognitive science. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.25-37.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1994): Cognition without classical architecture. In: ' Synthese', vol. 100, pp.291-306.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1995): Chaos and free will. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp.365-74.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1995): Chaos and free will. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 8, pp.365-74.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1996): Cognition poised at the edge of chaos: A complex alternative to a symbolic mind. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 9, pp.301-22.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1997): Syntax in a dynamic brain. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 110, pp.343-55.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1997): Syntax in a dynamic brain. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 110, pp.343-355.
@

Garson, J. W.

(1998): Chaotic emergence and the language of thought. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 11, pp.303-315.
@

Garzon, F.

(2000): A connectionist defence of the inscrutability thesis. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 15, pp.465-480.
@

Garzon, F.

(2000): State space semantics and conceptual similarity: reply to Churchland . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.77-96.
@

Garzon, F. C.

(2001): Can we turn a blind eye to eliminativism?. In: ' International Journal of Philosophical Studies', vol. 9, pp.485-498.
@

Gates, G.

(2001): Physicalism, empiricism, and positivism. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Gauker, C.

(1987): Mind and chance. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 17, pp.533-52.
@

Gauker, C.

(1988): Objective interpretationism. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 69, pp.136-51.
@

Gauker, C.

(1990): How to learn language like a chimpanzee. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.139-46.
@

Gauker, C.

(1991): Mental content and the division of epistemic labour. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 69, pp.302-18.
@

Gauker, C.

(1993): Holism without meaning: A critical review of Fodor and Lepore's Holism: A Shopper's Guide. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 6, pp.441-49.
@

Gauker, C.

(1993): An extraterrestrial perspective on conceptual development. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 8, pp.105-30.
@

Gauker, C.

(1995): Thinking Out Loud: An Essay on the Relation between Thought and Language . Princeton University Press.
@

Gauker, C.

(1995): A new skeptical solution. In: 'Acta Analytica: ', vol. 113.
@

Gauker, C.

(2003): Attitudes without psychology. In: 'Facta Philosophica ', vol. 5, pp.239-56.
@

Gauker, C.

(2003): Social externalism and linguistic communication. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Geach, P.

(1957): Mental Acts. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1990): Compositionality: A connectionist variation on a classical theme . In: 'Cognitive Science', vol. 14, pp.355-84.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1991): Classical questions, radical answers. In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1991): What is the D in PDP?. In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1993): The distinction between mind and cognition. In: Y. Houng; J. Ho (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition: 1993 International Symposium'. Academia Sinica.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1995): What might cognition be if not computation?. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 92, pp.345-81.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1995): What might cognition be if not computation?. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 92, pp.345-81.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1997): Connectionism, dynamics, and the philosophy of mind. In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind'. Pittsburgh University Press.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1998): Monism, dualism, pluralism. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp.76-97.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1998): The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 21, pp.615-28.
@

Gelder, van, T.

(1998): The roles of philosophy in cognitive science. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 11, pp.117-36.
@

Gelder, van, T.; Port, R.

(1995): Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition . MIT Press.
@

Gendler, T.

(2002): Personal identity and thought-experiments. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 52, pp.34-54.
@

Gendron, B.

(1970): On the relation of neurological and psychological theories: A critique of the hardware thesis. In: ' Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 8, pp.483-95.
@

Gennaro, R. J.

(1992): Consciousness, self-consciousness, and episodic memory. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 5, pp.333-47.
@

Georgalis, N.

(1990): No access for the externalist: Discussion of Heil's "Privileged access". In: 'Mind ', vol. 100, pp.101-8.
@

Georgalis, N.

(1994): Asymmetry of access to intentional states. In: ' Erkenntnis', vol. 40, pp.185-211.
@

Georgalis, N.

(1999): Rethinking Burge's thought experiment. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 118, pp.145-64.
@

George, A.; Velleman, D. J.

(2000): Leveling the playing field between mind and machine: A reply to McCall. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 97, pp.456-452.
@

George, F.

(1962): Minds, machines and Godel: Another reply to Mr. Lucas. In: 'Philosophy', vol. 37, pp.62-63.
@

Gerrans, P.

(2002): The theory of mind module in evolutionary psychology. In: 'Biology and Philosophy', vol. 17, pp.305-21.
@

Gerrans, P.

(2002): A one-stage explanation of the Cotard delusion. In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology', vol. 9, pp.47-53.
@

Gerrans, P.

(2003): Nativism and neuroconstructivism in the explanation of Williams syndrome . In: 'Biology and Philosophy', vol. 18, pp.41-52.
@

Gerrans, P.

(2004): Cognitive architecture and the limits of interpretationism. In: 'Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 11, pp.42-48.
@

Gertler, B.

(2000): The mechanics of self-knowledge. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 28, pp.125-46.
@

Gertler, B.

(2000): Functionalism's methodological predicament. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 38, pp.77-94.
@

Gertler, B.

(2003): Self-knowledge. In: '2003'.
@

Gertler, B.

(2003): Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge. Ashgate.
@

Gertler, B.

(2004): We can't know a priori that H2O exists. But can we know a priori that water does?. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 64, pp.44-47.
@

Gianfranco, S.

(2002): Reply to 'From simulation to theory'. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Gibb, S. C.

(2004): The problem of mental causation and the nature of properties. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 82, pp.464-75.
@

Gibbard, A.

(1996): Thoughts, norms, and discursive practices: Commentary on Brandom . In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.699-717.
@

Gibbard, A.

(2002): Normative explanations: Invoking rationality to explain happenings . In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature'. Clarendon.
@

Gibbard, A.

(2003): Thoughts and norms. In: 'Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp.83-98.
@

Gibbons, J.

(1993): Identity without supervenience. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 70, pp.59-79.
@

Gibbons, J.

(1996): Externalism and knowledge of content. In: ' Philsophical Review', vol. 105, pp.287-310.
@

Gibbons, J.

(2001): Externalism and knowledge of the attitudes. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 51, pp.13-28.
@

Gibson, J. J.

(1979): The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Houghton Mifflin.
@

Gibson, M.

(1996): Asymmetric dependencies, ideal conditions, and meaning. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 9, pp.235-59.
@

Gilbert, M.

(2002): Belief and acceptance as features of groups. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 16, pp.35-69.
@

Gilbert, P.

(1987): Westphal and Wittgenstein on white. In: 'Mind ', vol. 76, pp.399-403.
@

Gilbert, P.

(1989): Reflections on white: A rejoinder to Westphal. In: 'Mind ', vol. 98, pp.423-6.
@

Gill, J. H.

(1980): Of split brains and tacit knowing. In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 20, pp.49-58.
@

Gillett, C.

(2001): The methodological role of physicalism: A minimal skepticism. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Gillett, C.

(2003): The metaphysics of realization, multiple realizability, and the special sciences. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 100, pp.591-603.
@

Gillett, C.

(2003): Nonreductive realization and nonreductive identity: What physicalism does not entail. In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Gillett, C.; Loewer, B.

(2001): Physicalism and its Discontents. Cambridge University Press.
@

Gillett, C.; Rives, B.

(2001): Does the argument from realization generalize? Responses to Kim. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 39, pp.79-98.
@

Gillett, G.

(1986): Brain bisection and personal identity. In: 'Mind ', vol. 95, pp.224-9.
@

Gillett, G.

(1986): Multiple personality and the concept of a person. In: ' New Ideas in Psychology', vol. 4, pp.173-84.
@

Gillett, G.

(1987): Reasoning about persons. In: A. Peacocke; G. Gillett (Ed.): 'Persons and Personality: A Contemporary Inquiry'. Blackwell.
@

Gillett, G.

(1989): Representations and cognitive science. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 32, pp.261-77.
@

Gillett, G.

(1991): The neurophilosophy of pain. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp.191-206.
@

Gillett, G.

(1992): Representation, Meaning, and Thought. Oxford University Press.
@

Gillett, G.

(1995): Humpty Dumpty and the night of the triffids: Individualism and rule-following. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 105, pp.191-206.
@

Gillett, G.

(1997): A discursive account of multiple personality disorder. In: 'Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 4, pp.213-22.
@

Gillett, G.

(2001): Free will and events in the brain. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 22, pp.287-310.
@

Gilman, D.

(1993): Optimization and simplicity: Marr's theory of vision and biological explanation. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 107, pp.293-323.
@

Ginet, C.

(1980): The conditional analysis of freedom. In: P. van Inwagen (Ed.): 'Time and Cause: Essays Presented to Richard Taylor'. Reidel.
@

Ginet, C.

(1983): In defense of incompatibilism. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 44, pp.391-400.
@

Ginet, C.

(1989): Reasons explanation of action: An incompatibilist account. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 3.
@

Ginet, C.

(1990): On Action. Cambridge University Press.
@

Ginet, C.

(1992): The dispositionalist solutions to Wittgenstein's problem about understanding a rule: Answering Kripke's objection . In: 'Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 17.
@

Ginet, C.

(1996): In defense of the principle of alternative possibilities: Why I don't find Frankfurt's argument convincing. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 10, pp.403-17.
@

Ginet, C.

(2002): Reasons and explanations of action: Causalist versus noncausalist accounts . In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Gips, J.

(1994): Toward the ethical robot. In: K. M. Ford; C. Glymour; P. Hayes (Ed.): 'Android Epistemology'. MIT Press.
@

Giunti, M.

(1995): Dynamic models of cognition. In: T. van Gelder; R. Port (Ed.): 'Mind as Motion'. MIT Press.
@

Giunti, M.

(1996): Computers, Dynamical Systems, and the Mind. Oxford University Press.
@

Gjelsvik, O.

(1991): Dretske on knowledge and content. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 86, pp.425-41.
@

Glasgow, J. I.

(1993): The imagery debate revisited: A computational perspective. In: 'Computational Intelligence', vol. 9, pp.310-33.
@

Glasgow, W. D.; Pilkington, G. W.

(1970): Other minds on evidential necessity. In: 'Mind', vol. 79, pp.431-35.
@

Glennan, S. S.

(1995): Computationalism and the problem of other minds. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 8, pp.375-88.
@

Glennan, S. S.

(1995): Computationalism and the problem of other minds. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 8, pp.375-88.
@

Globus, G.

(1984): Can methodological solipsism be confined to psychology?. In: 'Cognition and Brain Theory', vol. 7, pp.233-46.
@

Globus, G.

(1989): The strict identity theory of Schlick, Russell, Maxwell, and Feigl . In: M. Maxwell; C. Savage (Ed.): 'Science, Mind, and Psychology: Essays in Honor of Grover Maxwell'. University Press of America.
@

Globus, G.

(1991): Deconstructing the Chinese room. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 12, pp.377-91.
@

Globus, G.

(1992): Toward a noncomputational cognitive science. In: ' Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience', vol. 4, pp.299-310.
@

Globus, G. G.

(1992): Derrida and connectionism: Differance in neural nets. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 5, pp.183-97.
@

Glock, H.

(2000): Animals, thoughts and concepts. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 123, pp.35-104.
@

Glock, H. J.; Preston, J. M.

(1995): Externalism and first-person authority. In: 'Monist', vol. 78, pp.515-33.
@

Glover, J.

(1988): I: The Philosophy and Psychology of Personal Identity. Penguin.
@

Gluer, K.

(1999): Sense and prescriptivity. In: 'Acta Analytica ', vol. 14.
@

Glymour, C.

(1988): AI is philosophy. In: J. Fetzer (Ed.): 'Aspects of AI'. D.
@

Glymour, C.

(1994): On the methods of cognitive neuropsychology. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 45, pp.815-35.
@

Glymour, C.

(2000): Android epistemology for babies. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 122, pp.53-68.
@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1986): Why semantic properties won't earn their keep. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 50, pp.223-36.
@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1989): Misinformation. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.533-50.
@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1991): Signal, decision, action. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 88, pp.709-22.
@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(1996): Complexity and the Function of Mind in Nature. Cambridge University Press.
@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(2002): On the evolution of representational and interpretive capacities . In: 'Monist', vol. 85, pp.50-69.
@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(2002): Environmental complexity and the evolution of cognition. In: R. Sternberg and J. Kaufman (Ed.): 'The Evolution of Intelligence'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Godfrey-Smith, P.

(2004): On folk psychology and mental representation. In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind'. Elsevier.
@

Godow, R.

(1976): Eliminative materialism and denotation. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 36.
@

Goel, V.

(1991): Notationality and the information processing mind. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.129-166.
@

Goguen, J.

(2004): Musical qualia, context, time and emotion. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 11.
@

Gold, I.

(1999): On Lewis on naming the colours. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 77, pp.365-370.
@

Gold, I.

(1999): Dispositions and the central problem of color. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 93, pp.21-44.
@

Gold, I.; Hohwy, J.

(2000): Rationality and schizophrenic delusion. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 15, pp.146-167.
@

Goldberg, B.

(1977): A problem with anomalous monism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 32, pp.175-80.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(1997): Self-ascription, self-knowledge, and the memory argument. In: 'Analysis', vol. 57, pp.211-19.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(1999): The relevance of discriminatory knowledge of content. In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 80, pp.136-56.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(1999): The psychology and epistemology of self-knowledge. In: 'Synthese', vol. 118, pp.165-201.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2000): Externalism and authoritative knowledge of content: A new incompatibilist strategy. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 100, pp.51-79.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2002): Belief and its linguistic expression: Toward a belief box account of first-person authority. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 1, pp.65-76.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2002): Do anti-individualistic construals of propositional attitudes capture the agent's conception?. In: 'Nous ', vol. 36, pp.597-621.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2003): On our alleged a priori knowledge that water exists. In: 'Analysis', vol. 63, pp.38-41.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2003): Anti-individualism, conceptual omniscience, and skepticism. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 116, pp.53-78.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2003): What do you know when you know your own thoughts?. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2005): (Nonstandard) lessons from world-switching cases. In: 'Philosophia', vol. 32, pp.85-131.
@

Goldberg, S. C.

(2005): The dialectical context of Boghossian's memory argument. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 35, pp.135-48.
@

Goldfarb, W.

(1982): Kripke on Wittgenstein on rules. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 82, pp.471-488.
@

Goldie, P.

(2000): The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford University Press.
@

Goldie, P.

(2004): Emotion, reason, and virtue. In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): ' Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality'. Oxford University Press.
@

Goldie, P.

(2004): Emotion, feeling, and knowledge of the world. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Goldman, A.

(1968): Actions, predictions, and books of life. In: '1968'.
@

Goldman, A.

(1969): The compatibility of mechanism and purpose. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 78, pp.468-82.
@

Goldman, A.

(1986): Constraints on representation. In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): 'The Representation of Knowledge and Belief'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Goldman, A.

(1989): Interpretation psychologized. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 4, pp.161-85.
@

Goldman, A.

(1992): The psychology of folk psychology. In: '1992'.
@

Goldman, A.

(1992): In defense of the simulation theory. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 7, pp.104-119.
@

Goldman, A.

(1996): Simulation and interpersonal utility. In: L. May; M. Friedman; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Mind and Morals: Essays on Ethics and Cognitive Science'. MIT Press.
@

Goldman, A.

(2000): Folk psychology and mental concepts. In: 'Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp.4-25.
@

Goldman, A.

(2002): Simulation theory and mental concepts. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Goldman, A.

(2002): The mentalizing folk. In: 'Protosociology ', vol. 16, pp.7-34.
@

Goldman, A.

(2006): Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience of Mindreading. Oxford University Press.
@

Goldstein, I.

(1980): Why people prefer pleasure to pain. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 55.
@

Goldstein, I.

(1989): Pleasure and pain: unconditional intrinsic values. In: '1989'.
@

Goldstein, I.

(1994): Identifying mental states: A celebrated hypothesis refuted. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 72, pp.46-62.
@

Goldstein, I.

(1999): Intersubjective properties by which we specify pain, pleasure, and other kinds of mental states. In: ' 1999'.
@

Gomberg, P.

(1975): Free will as ultimate responsibility. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 15, pp.205-12.
@

Good, I. J.

(1967): Human and machine logic. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 18, pp.145-6.
@

Good, I. J.

(1969): Godel's theorem is a red herring. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 19, pp.357-8.
@

Goodenough, J. M.

(1996): Parfit and the Sorites paradox. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 2, pp.113-20.
@

Goodman, R.

(1985): Cavell and the problem of other minds. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 13, pp.43-52.
@

Goodman, R. B.

(1974): A note on eliminative materialism. In: ' Journal of Critical Analysis', vol. 5, pp.80-83.
@

Gopnik, A.

(1990): Developing the idea of intentionality: Children's theories of mind . In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.89-114.
@

Gopnik, A.

(1997): The scientist as child. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 63, pp.485-514.
@

Gopnik, A.

(2003): The theory theory as an alternative to the innateness hypothesis. In: L. Antony (Ed.): 'Chomsky and His Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Gopnik, A. and Meltzoff, AN.

(1998): Theories vs. modules: To the max and beyond. A reply to Poulin-Dubois and to Stich and Nichols. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.450-456.
@

Gopnik, A.; Wellman, H.

(1992): Why the child's theory of mind really is a theory. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 7, pp.145-71.
@

Gopnik, A.; Wellman, H. M.

(1995): Why the child's theory of mind really is a theory . In: '1995'.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(1974): The aboutness of emotions. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 27, pp.11-36.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(1986): Folk psychology as simulation. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 1, pp.158-71.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(1986): The passivity of emotions. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 95, pp.339-60.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(1987): The Structure of Emotions: Investigations in Cognitive Philosophy . Cambridge University Press.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(1992): The simulation theory: objections and misconceptions. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 7, pp.11-34.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(1995): Simulation without introspection or inference from me to you. In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation'. Blackwell.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(1996): Sympathy, simulation, and the impartial spectator. In: L. May; M. Friedman; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Mind and Morals: Essays on Ethics and Cognitive Science'. MIT Press.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(1996): `Radical' simulationism. In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Gordon, R. M.

(2000): Sellars's Rylean ancestors revisited. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 14, pp.102-114.
@

Gordon, R. M.; Barker, J. A.

(1994): Autism and the "theory of mind" debate. In: G. Graham; G. L. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology'. MIT Press.
@

Goschke, T.; Koppelberg, D.

(1990): Connectionism and the semantic content of internal representation. In: ' Review of International Philosophy', vol. 44, pp.87-103.
@

Goschke, T.; Koppelberg, D.

(1991): The concept of representation and the representation of concepts in connectionist models. In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Gosselin, P.

(1987): The principle of alternative possibilities. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 17, pp.91-104.
@

Gottlieb, D. F.

(1983): Wittgenstein's critique of the "Tractatus" view of rules. In: 'Synthese', vol. 56, pp.239-251.
@

Goudge, T. A.

(1982): Ryle's last thoughts on thinking. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 21, pp.125-32.
@

Gould, J. L.; Gould, C. G.

(1982): The insect mind: Physics or metaphysics?. In: D. Griffin (Ed.): 'Animal Mind -- Human Mind'. Springer-Verlag.
@

Gould, J. L.; Gould, C. G.

(1994): The Animal Mind. Scientific American Library.
@

Gozzano, S.

(1995): Consciousness and understanding in the Chinese room. In: 'Informatica', vol. 19, pp.653-56.
@

Graham, G,; Stephens, L.

(1994): Philosophical Psychopathology. MIT Press.
@

Graham, G.

(1982): Spartans and behaviorists. In: 'Behaviorism ', vol. 10.
@

Graham, G.

(1987): The origins of folk psychology. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 30, pp.357-79.
@

Graham, G.

(1993): Philosophy of Mind: An Introduction. Blackwell.
@

Graham, G.; Horgan, T.

(1988): How to be realistic about folk psychology. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 1.
@

Graham, G.; Horgan, T.

(1992): Southern fundamentalism and the end of philosophy. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Truth and Rationality'. Ridgeview.
@

Graham, G.; Stephens, G.

(1987): Minding your P's and Q's: Pain and sensible qualities . In: 'Nous', vol. 21, pp.395-405.
@

Graham, G.; Stephens, L.

(1994): An introduction to philosophical psychopathology: Its nature, scope, and emergence. In: G. Graham; L. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology'. MIT Press.
@

Grahek, N.

(1991): Objective and subjective aspects of pain. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.249-66.
@

Grahek, N.

(1995): The sensory dimension of pain. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 79, pp.167-84.
@

Grandy, R.

(1987): Information-based epistemology, ecological epistemology and epistemology naturalized. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 70, pp.191-203.
@

Grandy, R. E.

(1989): Concepts, prototypes, and information. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Grantham, T. A.; Nichols, S.

(1999): Evolutionary psychology: Ultimate explanations and Panglossian predictions. In: V. Hardcastle (Ed.): ' Where Biology Meets Psychology'. MIT Press.
@

Gray, R.

(2001): Cognitive modules, synaesthesia and the constitution of psychological natural kinds. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.65-82.
@

Green, O.

(1992): The Emotions: A Philosophical Theory. Kluwer.
@

Greene, R.

(2003): Constitutive theories of self-knowledge and the regress problem. In: 'Philosophical Papers', vol. 32, pp.141-48.
@

Greenspan, P. S.

(1978): Behavior control and freedom of action. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 87, pp.225-40.
@

Greenspan, P. S.

(1988): Emotions and Reasons: An Enquiry into Emotional Justification . Routledge.
@

Greenspan, P. S.

(1993): Free will and the genome project. In: ' Philosophy and Public Affairs', vol. 22, pp.31-43.
@

Greenspan, P. S.

(2004): Emotions, rationality, and mind-body. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1991): Reasons to believe. In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): ' The Future of Folk Psychology'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1991): Self-knowledge: Looking in the wrong direction. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.35-47.
@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1991): The Future of Folk Psychology: Intentionality and Cognitive Science . Cambridge University Press.
@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1992): Against eliminative materialism: from folk psychology to Volkerpsychologie. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 5, pp.349-68.
@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1993): Split brains and singular personhood. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 31, pp.285-306.
@

Greenwood, J. D.

(1999): Simulation, theory-theory and cognitive penetration: No "instance of the fingerpost". In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 14, pp.32-56.
@

Griffin, D. R.

(1982): Animal Mind -- Human Mind. Springer-Verlag.
@

Griffin, D. R.

(1984): Animal Thinking. Harvard University Press.
@

Griffin, D. R.

(1992): Animal Minds. University of Chicago Press.
@

Griffiths, A.

(1995): Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychiatry. Cambridge University Press.
@

Griffiths, A. P.

(1989): Is free will incompatible with something or other?. In: 'Philosophy', vol. 24, pp.101-19.
@

Griffiths, P. E.

(1989): Folk, functional and neurochemical aspects of mood. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 2, pp.17-32.
@

Griffiths, P. E.

(1997): What Emotions Really Are: The Problem of Psychological Categories . University of Chicago Press.
@

Griffiths, P. E.

(2002): Emotions. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Griffiths, P. E.

(2003): Basic emotions, complex emotions, Machiavellian emotions. In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Griffiths, P. E.

(2004): Toward a "Machiavellian" theory of emotional appraisal. In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): 'Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality'. Oxford University Press.
@

Griffiths, P. E.

(2004): Is emotion a natural kind?. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Grim, P.

(1997): Worlds by supervenience: Some further problems. In: ' Analysis', vol. 2, pp.146-51.
@

Grim, P.; St. Denis, P.; Kokalis, T.

(2004): Information and meaning: Use-based models in arrays of neural nets. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 14, pp.43-66.
@

Grimaltos, T.

(2003): Terms and content. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): ' Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Grimes, T.

(1988): The myth of supervenience. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 69, pp.152-60.
@

Grimes, T.

(1991): Supervenience, determination, and dependency. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 62, pp.81-92.
@

Grimes, T.

(1995): The Tweedledum and Tweedledee of supervenience. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Grunbaum, A.

(1971): Free will and the laws of human behavior. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 8, pp.299-317.
@

Grunbaum, A.

(1972): Abelson on Feigl's mind-body identity thesis. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 23, pp.119-21.
@

Grunbaum, A.

(1994): The placebo concept in medicine and psychiatry. In: G. Graham; L. Stephens (Ed.): 'Philosophical Psychopathology'. MIT Press.
@

Grush, R.

(1997): The architecture of representation. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 10, pp.5-23.
@

Grush, R.

(2001): The semantic challenge to computational neuroscience. In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences'. University of Pittsburgh Press.
@

Grush, R.

(2003): In defense of some "Cartesian" assumption concerning the brain and its operation. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 18, pp.53-92.
@

Grush, R.; Churchland, P.

(1995): Gaps in Penrose's toiling. In: T. Metzinger (Ed.): 'Conscious Experience'. Ferdinand Schoningh.
@

Guarini, M.

(1996): Tensor products and split-level architecture: Foundational issues in the classicism-connectionism debate. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 63.
@

Guarini, M.

(2001): A defence of connectionism against the "syntactic" argument. In: 'Synthese', vol. 128, pp.287-317.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(1980): Functionalism, information and content. In: ' Nature and System', vol. 2, pp.139-62.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(1980): Rationality and the anomalous nature of the mental. In: 'Philosophy Research Archives', vol. 7.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(1982): Mental representation: A functionalist view. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 63, pp.3-20.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(1982): Functionalism as a theory of mind. In: ' Philosophy Research Archives', vol. 185.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(1989): Metaphysical arguments for internalism and why they don't work . In: S. Silvers (Ed.): 'ReRepresentation'. Kluwer.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(1992): Nonreductive materialism and the nature of intertheoretical constraint. In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism'. De Gruyter.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(1993): Who's in charge here? And who's doing all the work?. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(1994): Are beliefs brain states? And if they are what might that explain? . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 76, pp.205-15.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(2000): Inward and upward: Reflection, introspection, and self-awareness . In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 28, pp.275-305.
@

Gulick, van, R.

(2001): Reduction, emergence and other recent options on the mind/body problem: A philosophic overview. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 8, pp.1-34.
@

Gunderson, K.

(1964): The imitation game. In: 'Mind ', vol. 73, pp.234-45.
@

Gunderson, K.

(1968): Robots, consciousness and programmed behaviour. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 19, pp.109-22.
@

Gunderson, K.

(1969): Cybernetics and mind-body problems. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 12, pp.406-19.
@

Gunderson, K.

(1971): Mentality and Machines. Doubleday.
@

Gunther, Y.

(2003): Emotion and force. In: Y. Gunther (Ed.): ' Essays on Nonconceptual Content'. MIT Press.
@

Gunther, Y.

(2004): The phenomenology and intentionality of emotion. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 117, pp.43-55.
@

Gustafson, D.

(1995): Belief in pain. In: 'Consciousness and Cognition ', vol. 4, pp.323-45.
@

Gustafson, D.

(2000): On the supposed utility of a folk theory of pain. In: 'Brain and Mind', vol. 1, pp.223-228.
@

Gustafson, D. F.

(1963): On the identity theory. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 24, pp.30-32.
@

Guttenplan, S.

(1994): Belief, knowledge, and the origins of content. In: ' Dialectica', vol. 48, pp.287-305.
@

Guttenplan, S.

(2000): Mind's Landscape: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Blackwell Publishers.

H


@

Hacker, P. M. S.

(1972): Other minds and Professor Ayer's concept of a person. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 32, pp.341-354.
@

Hacking, I.

(1985): Rules, scepticism, proof, Wittgenstein. In (I. In: '1985 '.
@

Hacking, I.

(1991): Two souls in one body. In: 'Critical Inquiry ', vol. 17, pp.838-67.
@

Hacking, I.

(1993): On Kripke's and Goodman's uses of 'grue'. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 68.
@

Hacking, I.

(1995): Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and the Sciences of Memory . Princeton University Press.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1987): Godel, Lucas, and mechanical models of mind. In: ' Computational Intelligence', vol. 3, pp.57-63.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1990): Truth conditions and procedural semantics. In: P. Hanson (Ed.): 'Information, Language and Cognition'. University of British Columbia Press.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1990): Connectionism, rule-following, and symbolic manipulation. In: '1990'.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1991): The many uses of `belief' in AI. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.55-74.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1993): Connectionism, explicit rules, and symbolic manipulation. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 3.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1994): Systematicity in connectionist language learning. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.247-72.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1994): Systematicity revisited. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 9, pp.431-44.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1995): The `explicit-implicit' distinction. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.219-42.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1997): Cognition, systematicity, and nomic necessity. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.137-53.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1997): Cognition, systematicity, and nomic necessity. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.137-53.
@

Hadley, R. F.

(1997): Explaining systematicity: A reply to Kenneth Aizawa. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 12, pp.571-79.
@

Hadley, R. F.; Hayward, M. B.

(1997): Strong semantic systematicity from Hebbian connectionist learning. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp.1-55.
@

Hahn, M.

(2003): When swampmen get arthritis: "Externalism" in Burge and Davidson. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Hahn, M.; Ramberg, B.

(2003): Reflections and Replies: Essays on the Philosophy of Tyler Burge. MIT Press.
@

Haight, D.; Haight, M.

(1989): Time, memory, and self-remembering. In: ' Journal of Speculative Philosophy', vol. 3, pp.1-11.
@

Hajek, A.; Pettit, P.

(2004): Desire beyond belief. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 82, pp.77-92.
@

Haji, I.

(2002): Compatibilist views of freedom and responsibility. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Haji, I.; Cuypers, S.

(2001): Libertarian free will and CNC manipulation. In: 'Dialectica', vol. 55, pp.221-238.
@

Haldane, J.

(1988): Understanding folk. In: 'Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 62, pp.222-46.
@

Haldane, J.

(1996): The mystery of emergence. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 96, pp.261-67.
@

Haldane, J.

(2000): The state and fate of contemporary philosophy of mind. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 37, pp.301-21.
@

Haldane, J. J.

(1989): Naturalism and the problem of intentionality. In: ' Inquiry', vol. 32, pp.305-22.
@

Haldane, J. J.

(1994): Analytical philosophy and the nature of mind: Time for another rebirth?. In: R. Warner; T. Szubka (Ed.): ' The Mind-Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate'. Blackwell.
@

Hale, B.

(1997): Rule-following, objectivity and meaning. In: B. Hale; C. Wright (Ed.): 'A Companion to the Philosophy of Language'. Blackwell.
@

Hall, L.

(1998): The self-knowledge that externalists leave out. In: ' Southwest Philosophy Review', vol. 14.
@

Hall, R. J.

(1989): Are pains necessarily unpleasant?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 49, pp.643-59.
@

Hall, R. J.

(1996): The evolution of color vision without colors. In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement', vol. 63, pp.125-33.
@

Hamer, C.

(1970): Why Ryle is not a behaviourist. In: ' Philosophical Studies (Ireland)', vol. 17, pp.7-25.
@

Hamilton, A.

(1995): A new look at personal identity. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 45, pp.332-349.
@

Hamlyn, D. W.

(1953): Behaviour. In: 'Philosophy', vol. 28, pp.132-45.
@

Hampshire, S.

(1952): The analogy of feeling. In: 'Mind ', vol. 61, pp.1-12.
@

Hanfling, O.

(1984): What does the private language argument prove?. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 34, pp.468-481.
@

Hanfling, O.

(1985): Was Wittgenstein a sceptic?. In: ' Philosophical Investigations', vol. 8, pp.1-16.
@

Hanna, P.

(1985): Causal powers and cognition. In: 'Mind ', vol. 94, pp.53-63.
@

Hannan, B.

(1990): `Non-scientific realism' about propositional attitudes as a response to eliminativist arguments. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 18, pp.21-31.
@

Hannan, B.

(1993): Don't stop believing: the case against eliminative materialism. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 8, pp.165-179.
@

Hannay, A.

(1971): Mental Images: A Defense. Allen & Unwin.
@

Hannay, A.

(1973): To see a mental image. In: 'Mind ', vol. 82, pp.161-262.
@

Hannay, B.

(1994): Subjectivity and Reduction: An Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem . Westview Press.
@

Hanratty, G.

(1972): The identity theory of Herbert Feigl. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 20, pp.113-23.
@

Hanson, N. R.

(1952): Professor Ryle's "mind". In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 2, pp.246-48.
@

Hanson, S.; Burr, D.

(1990): What connectionist models learn. In: '1990 '.
@

Hanson, W.

(1971): Mechanism and Godel's theorem. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 22, pp.9-16.
@

Hardcastle, V.

(1996): How to Build a Theory in Cognitive Science. SUNY Press.
@

Hardcastle, V.

(2002): On the normativity of functions. In: A. Ariew (Ed.): ' Functions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Hardcastle, V.

(2003): Emotions and narrative selves. In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 10, pp.353-356.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1992): Reduction, explanatory extension, and the mind/brain sciences . In: '<i>Philosophy of Science</i>', vol. 59, pp.408-28.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1992): Reduction, explanatory extension, and the mind/brain sciences . In: '<i>Philosophy of Science</i>', vol. 59, pp.408-28.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1994): Indicator semantics and Dretske's function. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.367-82.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1995): Computationalism. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 105, pp.303-17.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1997): is explanation better. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 64, pp.154-60.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1997): When a pain is not. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 94, pp.381-409.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1998): On the matter of minds and mental causation. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 58, pp.1-25.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(1999): Where Biology Meets Psychology: Philosophical Essays. MIT Press.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.

(2000): The Myth of Pain. MIT Press.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.; Stewart, C. M.

(2001): Theory structure in neuroscience. In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences'. University of Pittsburgh Press.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.; Stewart, C. M.

(2002): What do brain data really show?. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 69, pp.572-582.
@

Hardcastle, V. G.; Stewart, C. M.

(2004): Neuroscience and the art of single-cell recordings . In: 'Biology and Philosophy', vol. 18, pp.195-208.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1983): Colors, normal observers and standard conditions. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 80, pp.806-13.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1984): A new look at color. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 21, pp.125-33.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1984): Are scientific objects colored?. In: 'Mind ', vol. 93, pp.491-500.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1985): The resemblances of colors. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 48, pp.35-47.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1985): Frank talk about the colors of sense-data. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 63, pp.485-93.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1988): Color for Philosophers. Hackett.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1988): Phenomenal colors and sorites. In: 'Nous ', vol. 22, pp.213-34.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1989): Could white be green?. In: 'Mind ', vol. 390, pp.285-8.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1989): Idle colors and busy spectra. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 49, pp.47-8.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1990): Color and illusion. In: W. Lycan (Ed.): ' Mind and Cognition'. Blackwell.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(1993): van Brakel and the not-so-naked emperor. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 44, pp.137-50.
@

Hardin, C. L.

(2004): A green thought in a green shade. In: '2004'.
@

Hare, R. M.

(1984): Supervenience. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 58, pp.1-16.
@

Harman, G.

(1969): Linguistic competence and empiricism. In: S. Hook (Ed.): ' Language and Philosophy'. New York University Press.
@

Harman, G.

(1973): Thought. Princeton University Press.
@

Harman, G.

(1974): Meaning and semantics. In: M. Munitz; P. Unger (Ed.): ' Semantics and Philosophy'. New York University Press.
@

Harman, G.

(1975): Language, thought, and communication. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 7, pp.270-298.
@

Harman, G.

(1975): Language, thought, and communication. In: K. Gunderson (Ed.): 'Language, Mind, and Knowledge'. University of Minnesota Press.
@

Harman, G.

(1977): How to use propositions. In: '1977'.
@

Harman, G.

(1978): Is there mental representation?. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 9.
@

Harman, G.

(1982): Conceptual role semantics. In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic', vol. 28, pp.242-56.
@

Harman, G.

(1986): Change in View. MIT Press.
@

Harman, G.

(1989): Some philosophical issues in cognitive science. In: M. Posner (Ed.): 'Foundations of Cognitive Science'. MIT Press.
@

Harnad, S.

(1982): Neoconstructivism: A unifying constraint for cognitive science. In: T. Simon; R. Scholes (Ed.): 'Language, Mind, and Brain'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Harnad, S.

(1989): Minds, machines and Searle. In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 1, pp.5-25.
@

Harnad, S.

(1990): Lost in the hermeneutical hall of mirrors. In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 2, pp.321-27.
@

Harnad, S.

(1990): The symbol grounding problem. In: 'Physica D ', vol. 42, pp.335-346.
@

Harnad, S.

(1991): Other bodies, other minds: A machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.43-54.
@

Harnad, S.

(1991): Other bodies, other minds: A machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.43-54.
@

Harnad, S.

(1992): Connecting object to symbol in modeling cognition. In: A. Clark; R. Lutz (Ed.): 'Connectionism in Context'. Springer-Verlag.
@

Harnad, S.

(1994): Levels of functional equivalence in reverse bioengineering: The Darwinian Turing test for artificial life. In: 'Artificial Life', vol. 1, no.3.
@

Harnad, S.

(1994): Computation is just interpretable symbol manipulation; Cognition isn't . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.379-90.
@

Harnad, S.

(1999): Turing on reverse-engineering the mind. In: '1999'.
@

Harnad, S.

(2002): Symbol grounding and the origin of language. In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): 'Computationalism: New Directions'. MIT Press.
@

Harnad, S.

(2003): Minds, machines, and Searle 2: What's right and wrong about the Chinese room argument. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Harnad, S.

(2003): Can a machine be conscious? How?. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 10.
@

Harrell, M.

(1996): Confirmation holism and semantic holism. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 109, pp.63-101.
@

Harris, E. E.

(1966): The neural identity thesis and the person. In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 6, pp.515-37.
@

Harris, H.

(1995): Identity. Oxford University Press.
@

Harris, H.

(1995): An experimentalist looks at identity. In: H. Harris (Ed.): ' Identity'. Oxford University Press.
@

Harrison, P.

(1991): Do animals feel pain?. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp.25-40.
@

Harvey, J.

(1992): Challenging the obvious: The logic of color concepts. In: 'Philosophia', vol. 21, pp.277-94.
@

Harvey, J.

(2000): Colour-dispositionalism and its recent critics. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 61, pp.137-156.
@

Harzem, P.

(2004): Behaviorism for new psychology: What was wrong with behaviorism and what is wrong with it now. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 32, pp.5-12.
@

Hasker, W.

(1982): Emergentism. In: 'Religious Studies ', vol. 18, pp.473-88.
@

Hasker, W.

(1999): The Emergent Self. Cornell University Press.
@

Hasker, W.

(1999): The Emergent Self. Cornell University Press.
@

Hasker, W.

(2004): The constitution view of persons: A critique. In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 44.
@

Hassrick, B.

(1995): Fred Dretske on the explanatory role of semantic content. In: 'Conference', vol. 6, pp.59-66.
@

Hatfield, G.

(1988): Neurophilosophy meets psychology: Reduction, autonomy, and empirical constraints. In: ' Cognitive Neuropsychology', vol. 5, pp.723-46.
@

Hatfield, G.

(1989): Computation, representation and content in noncognitive theories of perception. In: S. Silvers (Ed.): ' ReRepresentation'. Kluwer.
@

Hatfield, G.

(1990): Gibsonian representations and connectionist symbol-processing: prospects for unification. In: ' Psychological Research', vol. 52, pp.243-52.
@

Hatfield, G.

(1991): Representation and rule-instantiation in connectionist systems. In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Hatfield, G.

(1991): Representation in perception and cognition: Connectionist affordances . In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Hatfield, G.

(1999): Mental functions as constraints on neurophysiology: Biology and psychology of vision. In (V. Hardcastle, ed) Where Biology Meets Psychology: Philosophical Essays . In: '1999'.
@

Hatfield, G.

(2000): The brain's 'new' science: Psychology, neurophysiology, and constraint . In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 67, pp.388-404.
@

Hatfield, G.

(2002): Psychology, philosophy, and cognitive science: Reflections on the history and philosophy of experimental psychology . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 17, pp.207-232.
@

Hattiangadi, A.

(2003): Making it implicit: Brandom on rule-following. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 66, pp.419-31.
@

Hatzimoysis, A.

(2003): Philosophy and the Emotions. Cambridge University Press.
@

Hatzimoysis, A.

(2003): Emotional feelings and intentionalism. In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1978): The nature and plausibility of cognitivism. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 1, pp.215-26.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1979): Understanding natural language. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 76, pp.619-32.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1981): Semantic engines: An introduction to mind design. In: J. Haugeland (Ed.): 'Mind Design'. MIT Press.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1981): Mind Design. MIT Press.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1982): Weak supervenience. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 19, pp.93-103.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1984): Ontological supervenience. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 22, pp.1-12.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1987): An overview of the frame problem. In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): ' The Robot's Dilemma'. Ablex.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1990): The Intentionality All-Stars. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 4, pp.383-427.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1993): Pattern and being. In: B. Dahlbom (Ed.): ' Dennett and His Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1993): Mind embodied and embedded. In: Y. Houng; J. Ho (Ed.): ' Mind and Cognition:1993 International Symposium'. Academia Sinica.
@

Haugeland, J.

(1993): Mind embodied and embedded. In: Y. Houng; J. Ho (Ed.): ' Mind and Cognition:1993 International Symposium'. Academia Sinica.
@

Haugeland, J.

(2002): Authentic intentionality. In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): ' Computationalism: New Directions'. MIT Press.
@

Haugeland, J.

(2003): Syntax, semantics, physics. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Haugen, D.

(1995): Personal identity and concern for the future. In: ' Philosophia', vol. 24, pp.481-492.
@

Haukioja, J.

(2002): Soames and Zalabardo on Kripke's Wittgenstein. In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 64, pp.157-73.
@

Haukioja, J.

(2004): Is solitary rule-following possible?. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 32.
@

Haukioja, J.

(2006): Semantic externalism and a priori self-knowledge. In: ' Ratio', vol. 19.
@

Haukioja, J.

(2006): Semantic externalism and a priori self-knowledge. In: ' Ratio', vol. 19.
@

Haukioja, J.

(2006): Hindriks on rule-following. In: '2006'.
@

Hauser, L.

(1993): Reaping the whirlwind: Reply to Harnad's "Other bodies, other minds" . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 3, pp.219-37.
@

Hauser, L.

(1993): Why isn't my pocket calculator a thinking thing?. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 3, pp.3-10.
@

Hauser, L.

(1995): Natural language and thought: Doing without mentalese. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.41-47.
@

Hauser, L.

(1997): Searle's Chinese box: Debunking the Chinese room argument. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 7, pp.199-226.
@

Hauser, L.

(2001): Look who's moving the goal posts now. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 11, pp.41-51.
@

Hauser, L.

(2003): Nixin' goes to China. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): ' Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Hawthorne, J.

(1989): On the compatibility of connectionist and classical models. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 2, pp.5-16.
@

Hawthorne, J.

(2002): Blocking definitions of materialism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 110, pp.103-13.
@

Haybron, D. M.

(2000): The causal and explanatory role of information stored in connectionist networks. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 10, pp.361-380.
@

Haybron, D. M.

(2001): Happiness and pleasure. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 62, pp.501-528.
@

Hayes, P.

(1987): What the frame problem is and isn't. In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): ' The Robot's Dilemma'. Ablex.
@

Hayes, P. J.; Ford, K. M.; Adams-Webber, J. R.

(1994): Human reasoning about artificial intelligence. In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 4, pp.247-63.
@

Hayes, P.; Ford, K.

(1995): Turing test considered harmful. In: ' <i>Proceedings of the Fourteenth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence</i> ', vol. 1, pp.972-77.
@

Hayes, P.; Harnad, S.; Perlis, D.; Block, N.

(1992): Virtual symposium on virtual mind . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 2.
@

Hazen, A. P.

(1999): On naming the colours. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 77, pp.224-231.
@

Heal, J.

(1986): Replication and functionalism. In: J. Butterfield (Ed.): ' Language, Mind, and Logic'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Heal, J.

(1994): Semantic holism: Still a good buy. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 68, pp.325-39.
@

Heal, J.

(1994): Simulation vs. theory-theory: What is at issue?. In: C. Peacocke (Ed.): 'Objectivity, Simulation, and the Unity of Consciousness'. Oxford University Press.
@

Heal, J.

(1995): How to think about thinking. In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): ' Mental Simulation'. Blackwell.
@

Heal, J.

(1996): Simulation and cognitive penetrability. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 11, pp.44-67.
@

Heal, J.

(1996): Simulation, theory, and content. In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Heal, J.

(1997): Understanding other minds from inside. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Heal, J.

(1998): Externalism and memory. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 72, pp.77-94.
@

Heal, J.

(1998): Co-cognition and off-line simulation: Two ways of understanding the simulation approach. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.477-498.
@

Heal, J.

(2000): Other minds, rationality and analogy. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplement', vol. 74, pp.1-19.
@

Heal, J.

(2000): Other minds, rationality, and analogy. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 74, pp.1-19.
@

Heal, J.

(2000): Understanding other minds from the inside. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 14, pp.39-55.
@

Heal, J.

(2001): On first-person authority. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 102, pp.1-19.
@

Heal, J.

(2003): Mind, Reason, and Imagination: Selected Essays in Philosophy of Mind and Language. Cambridge University Press.
@

Heal, J.

(2005): Joint attention and understanding the mind. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, eds) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds . In: '2005'.
@

Hedman, C. G.

(1970): On correlating brain states with psychological states. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 48, pp.247-51.
@

Hedman, C. G.

(1970): On correlating brain states with psychological states. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 48, pp.247-51.
@

Heidelberger, H.

(1966): On characterizing the psychological. In: '1966 '.
@

Heil, J.

(1970): Sensations, experiences, and brain processes. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 45, pp.221-6.
@

Heil, J.

(1981): Does cognitive psychology rest on a mistake?. In: 'Mind ', vol. 90, pp.321-42.
@

Heil, J.

(1982): Speechless brutes. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 42, pp.400-406.
@

Heil, J.

(1986): Formalism and psychological explanation. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 7, pp.1-10.
@

Heil, J.

(1988): Privileged access. In: 'Mind', vol. 98, pp.238-51.
@

Heil, J.

(1992): The Nature of True Minds. Cambridge University Press.
@

Heil, J.

(1992): Mentality and causality. In: 'Topoi ', vol. 11, pp.103-110.
@

Heil, J.

(1995): Supervenience redux. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): ' Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Heil, J.

(1999): Multiple realizability. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 36, pp.189-208.
@

Heil, J.

(2002): Mental causation. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Heil, J.

(2003): Multiply realized properties. In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Heil, J.

(2004): Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. Oxford University Press.
@

Heil, J.; Martin, C. B.

(1998): Rules and powers. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 12, pp.283-312.
@

Heil, J.; Mele, A.

(1991): Mental causes. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 28, pp.61-71.
@

Heil, J.; Robb, D.

(2003): Mental properties. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 40, pp.175-196.
@

Heinaman, R.

(1986): Incompatibilism without the principle of alternative possibilities . In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 64, pp.266-76.
@

Heinimaa, M.

(2000): Ambiguities in the psychiatric use of the concepts of the person: An analysis. In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 7, pp.125-136.
@

Heitner, R.

(2000): Is design relative or real? Dennett on intentional relativism and physical realism. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 10, pp.267-83.
@

Heller, M.

(1991): Indication and what might have been. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 51, pp.187-91.
@

Heller, M.

(1996): The mad scientist meets the robot cats: Compatibilism, kinds, and counterexamples. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.333-37.
@

Hellman, G.

(1985): Determination and logical truth. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 82, pp.607-16.
@

Hellman, G.

(1992): Supervenience/determination a two-way street? Yes, but one of the ways is the wrong way!. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 89, pp.42-47.
@

Hellman, G.; Thomson, F.

(1975): Physicalism: ontology, determination and reduction. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 72, pp.551-64.
@

Hellman, G.; Thomson, F.

(1977): Physicalist materialism. In: 'Nous ', vol. 11, pp.309-45.
@

Helm, B. W.

(1994): The Significance of Emotions. American Philosophical Quarterly 31:319-31.
@

Hendel, G.

(2001): Physicalism, nothing buttery, and supervenience. In: ' Ratio', vol. 14, pp.252-262.
@

Hendel, G.

(2001): Supervenience, metaphysical reduction, and metaphysics of properties . In: 'Southern Journal Of Philosophy', vol. 39, pp.99-118.
@

Hendel, G.

(2001): Realization. In: 'Critica', vol. 33, pp.41-70.
@

Hendel, G.

(2002): On what does the issue of supervenience and psychophysical dependence depend?. In: ' Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review', vol. 41.
@

Henderson, D.

(1996): Simulation theory versus theory theory: A difference without a difference in explanations. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 34, pp.65-93.
@

Hendrichs, H.

(1999): Different roots of human intentionality in mammalian mentality . In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 51, pp.649-668.
@

Hendriks-Jansen, H.

(1996): Catching Ourselves in the Act: Situated Activity, Interactive Emergence, Evolution, and Human Thought. MIT Press.
@

Henle, P.

(1942): The status of emergence. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 39, pp.486-93.
@

Henley, T. B.

(1990): Natural problems and artificial intelligence. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 18, pp.43-55.
@

Herbert, R. T.

(1998): Dualism/materialism. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 48, pp.159-75.
@

Hershenov, D.

(2005): Do dead bodies pose a problem for biological approaches to personal identity?. In: 'Mind', vol. 114.
@

Herstein, G. L.

(2005): Davidson on the impossibility of psychophysical laws. In: 'Synthese', vol. 145, pp.45-63.
@

Hess, P.

(1981): Actions, reasons and Humean causes. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 41, pp.77-81.
@

Hilbert, D. R.

(1987): Color and Color Perception: A Study in Anthropocentric Realism . CSLI Press.
@

Hilbert, D. R.

(1992): What is color vision?. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 68, pp.351-70.
@

Hiley, D. R.

(1978): Is eliminative materialism materialistic?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 38, pp.325-37.
@

Hiley, D. R.

(1980): The disappearance theory and the denotation argument. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 37, pp.307-20.
@

Hill, C.

(2004): Ouch! An essay on pain. In: R. Gennaro (Ed.): ' Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness: An Anthology'. John Benjamins.
@

Hill, C. S.

(1984): In defense of type materialism. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 59, pp.295-320.
@

Hill, C. S.

(1984): Watsonian freedom and the freedom of the will. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 62, pp.294-98.
@

Hill, C. S.

(1992): Van Inwagen on the consequence argument. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 52, pp.49-55.
@

Hillis, D.

(1998): Can a machine be conscious?. In: S. Hameroff; A. Kaszniak; A. Scott (Ed.): 'Toward a Science of Consciousness II'. MIT Press.
@

Himma, K. E.

(2005): When a problem for all in a problem for none: Substance dualism, physicalism, and the mind-body problem. In: '2005'.
@

Hindriks, F.

(2004): A modest solution to the problem of rule-following. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 121, pp.65-98.
@

Hinton, J. M.

(1967): Illusions and identity. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 27, pp.65-76.
@

Hirsch, E.

(1991): Divided minds. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 1, pp.3-30.
@

Hirstein, W.

(2004): Brain Fiction: Self-Deception and the Riddle of Confabulation. MIT Press.
@

Hobart, R. E.

(1934): Free will as involving determinism and inconceivable without it . In: 'Mind', vol. 43, pp.1-27.
@

Hobson, J.

(2002): Sleep and dream suppression following a lateral medullary infarct: A first-person account. In: ' Consciousness and Cognition', vol. 11, pp.377-390.
@

Hockutt, M.

(1967): In defense of materialism. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 27, pp.366-85.
@

Hodgson, D.

(1991): The Mind Matters: Consciousness and Choice in a Quantum World. Oxford University Press.
@

Hodgson, D.

(2002): Consciousness, quantum physics, and free will. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Hodgson, D.

(2002): Physics, consciousness and free will. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Hodgson, D.

(2005): A plain person's free will. Journal of Consciousness Studies , vol. 12, no.1, pp.3-19.
@

Hoerl, C.

(1999): Memory, amnesia, and the past. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 14, pp.227-51.
@

Hoerl, C.

(2002): Reply to 'Neurophysiological evidence for simulation and action'. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Hoerl, C.; McCormack, T

(2001): Time and Memory: Philosophical Perspectives. Oxford University Press.
@

Hoerl, C.; McCormack, T.

(2005): Joint reminiscing as attention to the past. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, eds) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds . In: '2005'.
@

Hoffman, C. A.

(1993): Desires and the desirable. In: 'Philosophical Forum ', vol. 25, pp.19-32.
@

Hoffman, P.

(1985): Kripke on private language. In: 'Philosophical Studies: ', vol. 47, pp.23-28.
@

Hoffman, R.

(1960): The problem of other minds - genuine or pseudo?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 20, pp.503-512.
@

Hoffman, R.

(1967): Malcolm and Smart on brain-mind identity. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 42.
@

Hofstadter, D. R.

(1979): Godel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid. Basic Books.
@

Hofstadter, D. R.

(1981): A coffee-house conversation on the Turing test. In: '1981'.
@

Hofstadter, D. R.

(1981): Reflections on Searle. In: D. Hofstadter; D. Dennett (Ed.): 'The Mind's I'. @

Hofstadter, D. R.

(1983): Artificial intelligence: Subcognition as computation. In: F. Machlup (Ed.): ' The Study of Information: Interdisciplinary Messages'. Wiley.
@

Hogan, M.

(1994): What is wrong with an atomistic account of mental representation. In: 'Synthese', vol. 100, pp.307-27.
@

Hohwy, J.

(2001): Semantic primitivism and normativity. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 14, pp.1-17.
@

Hohwy, J.

(2002): Privileged self-knowledge and externalism: A contextualist approach . In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 83, pp.235-52.
@

Hohwy, J.

(2003): A reduction of Kripke-Wittgenstein's objections to dispositionalism about meaning. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 13, pp.257-68.
@

Hohwy, J.; Rosenberg, R.

(2005): Unusual experiences, reality testing and delusions of alien control. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 20.
@

Holland, O.; Goodman, R.

(2003): Robots with internal models: A route to machine consciousness?. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 10.
@

Holland, R. F.

(1954): The empiricist theory of memory. In: 'Mind ', vol. 63, pp.464-86.
@

Holman, E. L.

(2002): Color eliminativism and color experience. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quareterly', vol. 83, pp.38-56.
@

Holt, L.

(1999): Rationality is still hard work: Some further notes on the disruptive effects of deliberation. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 12, pp.215-219.
@

Holtzman, S.; Leich, C.

(1981): Wittgenstein: To Follow A Rule. Routledge.
@

Honderich, T.

(1973): Essays on Freedom of Action. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
@

Honderich, T.

(1981): Psychophysical law-like connections and their problems. In: 'Inquiry', vol. 24, pp.277-303.
@

Honderich, T.

(1982): The argument for anomalous monism. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 42, pp.59-64.
@

Honderich, T.

(1988): A Theory of Determinism. Oxford University Press.
@

Honderich, T.

(1993): The union theory and anti-individualism. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Honderich, T.

(1993): How Free Are You?. Oxford University Press.
@

Honderich, T.

(1996): Compatibilism, incompatibilism, and the smart aleck. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.855-62.
@

Honderich, T.

(2002): Determinism as true, compatibilism and incompatibilism as false, and the real alternative. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Honderich, T.

(2002): How Free Are You? The Determinism Problem. Oxford University Press. Honderich, T. 2002. Determinism as true, compatibilism and incompatibilism as both false, and the real problem . In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Hook, S.

(1958): Determinism and Freedom in the Age of Modern Science. In: ' 1958'.
@

Hooker, C. A.

(1975): The information-processing approach to the brain-mind and its philosophical ramifications. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 36, pp.1-15.
@

Hooker, C. A.; Christensen, W. D.

(1998): Towards a new science of the mind: Wide content and the metaphysics of organizational properties in nonlinear dynamic models . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.98-109.
@

Hope, T.

(1994): Personal Identity and Psychiatric Illness. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 37, pp.131-143.
@

Horgan, T.

(1981): Token physicalism, supervenience, and the generality of physics. In: 'Synthese', vol. 49, pp.395-413.
@

Horgan, T.

(1982): Supervenience and microphysics. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 63, pp.29-43.
@

Horgan, T.

(1984): Supervenience and cosmic hermeneutics. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 22, pp.19-38.
@

Horgan, T.

(1984): Functionalism and token physicalism. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 59, pp.321-38.
@

Horgan, T.

(1985): Compatibilism and the consequence argument. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 47, pp.339-56.
@

Horgan, T.

(1989): Mental quausation. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 3, pp.47-74.
@

Horgan, T.

(1991): Actions, reasons, and the explanatory role of content. In: B. McLaughlin (Ed.): 'Dretske and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Horgan, T.

(1993): The austere ideology of folk psychology. In: '1993'.
@

Horgan, T.

(1993): From supervenience to superdupervenience: Meeting the demands of a material world. In: 'Mind ', vol. 102, pp.555-86.
@

Horgan, T.

(1993): Nonreductive materialism and the explanatory autonomy of psychology . In: S. Wagner; R. Warner (Ed.): 'Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal'. University of Notre Dame Press.
@

Horgan, T.

(1994): Naturalism and intentionality. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 76, pp.301-26.
@

Horgan, T.

(1994): Nonreductive materialism. In: R. Warner; T. Szubka (Ed.): ' The Mind-Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate'. Blackwell.
@

Horgan, T.

(1997): Kim on mental causation and causal exclusion. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 11, pp.165-84.
@

Horgan, T.

(1997): Connectionism and the philosophical foundations of cognitive science . In: 'Metaphilosophy', vol. 28, pp.1-30.
@

Horgan, T.

(2001): Causal compatibilism and the exclusion problem. In: ' Theoria', vol. 16, pp.95-116.
@

Horgan, T.; Graham, G.

(1990): In defense of Southern Fundamentalism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 62, pp.107-134.
@

Horgan, T.; Henderson, D.

(2005): What does it take to be a true believer? Against the opulent ideology of eliminative materialism. In: C. Erneling; D. Johnson (Ed.): 'Mind as a Scientific Object'. Oxford University Press.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1987): Settling into a new paradigm. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 26, pp.97-113.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1989): Representation without rules. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 17, pp.147-74.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1990): Soft laws. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 15.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1991): Structured representations in connectionist systems? . In: '1991'.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1991): Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. Kluwer.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1992): Cognitive systems as dynamic systems. In: ' Topoi', vol. 11, pp.27-43.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1992): Levels of description in nonclassical cognitive science . In: 'Philosophy', vol. 34.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1994): Representations don't need rules: Reply to James Garson . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.1-24.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1994): A nonclassical framework for cognitive science. In: 'Synthese', vol. 101, pp.305-45.
@

Horgan, T.; Tienson, J.

(1996): Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. MIT Press.
@

Horgan, T.; Timmons, M.

(1993): Metaphysical naturalism, semantic normativity, and meta-semantic irrealism. In: 'Philosophical Issues ', vol. 4.
@

Horgan, T.; Tye, M.

(1985): Against the token identity theory. In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): 'Action and Events'. Blackwell.
@

Horgan, T.; Woodward, J.

(1985): Folk psychology is here to stay. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 94, pp.197-225.
@

Horgan, T.; and Tienson, J.

(1995): Connectionism and the commitments of folk psychology . In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.127-52.
@

Hornsby, J.

(1981): Which physical events are mental events?. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 55, pp.73-92.
@

Hornsby, J.

(1984): On functionalism, and on Jackson, Pargetter, and Prior on functionalism . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 46, pp.75-96.
@

Hornsby, J.

(1986): Physicalist thinking and conceptions of behaviour. In: P. Pettit; J. McDowell (Ed.): 'Subject, Thought, and Context'. Oxford University Press.
@

Hornsby, J.

(1992): Physics, biology, and common-sense psychology. In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism'. Oxford University Press.
@

Hornsby, J.

(1993): Agency and causal explanation. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): ' Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Hornsby, J.

(2001): Simple Mindedness: In Defense of Naive Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mind. Harvard University Press.
@

Horowitz, A.

(1992): Functional role and intentionality. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 58, pp.197-218.
@

Horowitz, A.

(1995): Putnam, Searle, and externalism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 81, pp.27-69.
@

Horowitz, A.

(2001): Contents just are in the head. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 54, pp.321-344.
@

Horst, S.

(1995): Eliminativism and the ambiguity of `belief'. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 104, pp.123-45.
@

Horst, S.

(1996): Symbols, Computation, and Intentionality: A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind. University of California Press.
@

Horst, S.

(1999): Symbols and computation: A critique of the computational theory of mind . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 9, pp.347-381.
@

Horsten, L.

(1995): The Church-Turing thesis and effective mundane procedures. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.1-8.
@

Horwich, P.

(1990): Wittgenstein and Kripke on the nature of meaning. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 5, pp.105-121.
@

Hospers, J.

(1950): Meaning and free will. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 10, pp.307-30.
@

Houghton, D.

(1997): Mental content and external representations: internalism, anti-internalism. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 47, pp.159-77.
@

Houng, Y.

(1990): Classicism, connectionism and the concept of level.
@

Howard, G. S.

(1993): Steps toward a science of free will. In: ' Counseling and Values', vol. 37, pp.116-28.
@

Hoy, R. C.

(1980): Dispositions, logical states, and mental occurrents. In: 'Synthese', vol. 44, pp.207-40.
@

Hubin, D. C.

(2003): Desires, whims, and values. In: 'Journal of Ethics ', vol. 7, pp.315-35.
@

Huby, P.

(1967): The first discovery of the free will issue. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 42, pp.333-62.
@

Huff, D.

(1981): Family resemblances and rule-governed behavior. In: ' Philosophical Investigations', vol. 4, pp.1-23.
@

Hulse, D.; Read, C.; Schroeder, T.

(2004): The impossibility of conscious desire. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 41, pp.73-80.
@

Hum, D. D.

(1998): Davidson's identity crisis. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 52, pp.45-61.
@

Humberstone, I. L.

(1987): Wanting as believing. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 17, pp.49-62.
@

Humberstone, I. L.

(1992): Some structural and logica l aspects of the notion of supervenience. In: 'Logical Analysis', vol. 35, pp.101-37.
@

Humphrey, J.

(1996): Kripke's Wittgenstein and the impossibility of private language: The same old story?. In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 21, pp.197-207.
@

Humphrey, J.

(1999): Quine, Kripke's Wittgenstein, simplicity and sceptical solutions . In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 37.
@

Humphrey, N.

(2003): The Inner Eye: Social Intelligence in Evolution. Oxford University Press.
@

Humphrey, N.

(2003): The Mind Made Flesh: Essays from the Frontiers of Psychology and Evolution. Oxford University Press.
@

Humphrey, N.; Dennett, D. C.

(1989): Speaking for ourselves. In: 'Raritan ', vol. 9, pp.68-98.
@

Humphreys, G. W.

(1986): Information-processing systems which embody computational rules: The connectionist approach. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 1, pp.201-12.
@

Humphreys, P.

(1996): Aspects of emergence. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp.53-71.
@

Humphreys, P.

(1997): How properties emerge. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 64, pp.1-17.
@

Humphreys, P.

(1997): Emergence, not supervenience. In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement', vol. 64, pp.337-45.
@

Hunter, D.

(2002): Mind-brain identity and the nature of states. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 79, pp.366-86.
@

Hunter, J.

(1971): Some questions about dreaming. In: 'Mind ', vol. 80, pp.70-92.
@

Hunter, J.

(1983): The difference between dreaming and being awake. In: ' Mind', vol. 92, pp.80-93.
@

Hurley, S.

(1998): Vehicles, contents, conceptual structure and externalism. In: 'Analysis', vol. 58, pp.1-6.
@

Hurley, S.

(2003): Animal action in the space of reasons. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 18, pp.231-256.
@

Hurley, S. L.

(1998): Vehicles, contents, conceptual structure, and externalism. In: 'Analysis', vol. 58, pp.1-6.
@

Hutchins, E.

(1995): Cognition in the Wild. MIT Press.
@

Hutchins, E.

(1995): Cognition in the Wild. MIT Press.
@

Huttemann, A.

(2004): What's Wrong with Microphysicalism. Routledge.
@

Hutto, D.

(2004): The limits of spectatorial folk psychology. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.548-73.
@

Hutton, A.

(1976): This Godel is killing me. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 3, pp.135-44.
@

Hyland, M. E.

(1995): Against nomological reductionism in psychology: A response to Robinson . In: 'New Ideas in Psychology', vol. 13, pp.9-11.
@

Hyman, J.

(2003): Pains and places. In: 'Philosophy', vol. 78, pp.5-24.
@

Hyslop, A.

(1973): Criteria and other minds. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 51, pp.105-14.
@

Hyslop, A.

(1976): Other minds as theoretical entities. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 54, pp.158-61.
@

Hyslop, A.

(1979): A multiple case inference and other minds. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 57, pp.330-36.
@

Hyslop, A.

(1995): Other Minds. Kluwer.
@

Hyslop, A.; Jackson, F. C.

(1972): The analogical inference to other minds. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 9, pp.168-76.

I


@

Ingarden, R.

(2002): Open systems and consciousness: A philosophical discussion. In: 'Open Systems & Information Dynamics', vol. 9, pp.125-151.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1974): A formal approach to the problem of free will and determinism . In: 'Theoria', vol. 24, pp.9-22.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1975): The incompatibility of free will and determinism. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 27, pp.185-99.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1978): Ability and responsibility. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 87, pp.201-24.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1980): Compatibilism and the burden of proof. In: ' Analysis', vol. 40, pp.98-100.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1983): An Essay on Free Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1989): When is the will free?. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 3.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1990): Logic and the free will problem. In: ' Social Theory and Practice', vol. 16, pp.277-90.
@

Inwagen, van P.

(1992): There is no such thing as addition. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 17, pp.138-159.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(1994): When the will is not free. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 75, pp.95-113.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(2000): Free will remains a mystery. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.1-20.
@

Inwagen, van, P.

(2004): The self: The incredulous stare articulated. In: ' Ratio', vol. 17, pp.478-91.
@

Irani, K. S.; Myers, G.

(1983): Emotion: Philosophical Studies. Haven.
@

Irvine, A. D.

(1983): Lucas, Lewis, and mechanism -- one more time. In: ' Analysis', vol. 43, pp.94-98.
@

Israel, D.; Perry, J.

(1990): What is information?. In: P. Hanson (Ed.): ' Information, Language and Cognition'. University of British Columbia Press.
@

Ivet, P.

(2002): Emotions, revision, and the explanation of emotional action. In: 'European Review of Philosophy', vol. 5.

J


@

Jack, A.

(1994): Materialism and supervenience. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 72, pp.426-43.
@

Jackendoff, R.

(1985): Information is in the mind of the beholder. In: ' Linguistics and Philosophy', vol. 8, pp.23-33.
@

Jackendoff, R.

(1989): What is a concept, that a person may grasp it?. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 4, pp.68-102.
@

Jackendoff, R.

(1991): The problem of reality. In: 'Nous ', vol. 25, pp.411-33.
@

Jackman, H.

(1998): Individualism and interpretation. In: ' Southwest Philosophy Review', vol. 14, pp.31-38.
@

Jackman, H.

(1999): Moderate holism and the instability thesis. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 36, pp.361-69.
@

Jackman, H.

(2000): Belief, rationality, and psychophysical laws. In: ' Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, Volume 9: Philsophy of Mind'.
@

Jackman, H.

(2003): Foundationalism, coherentism, and rule-following skepticism. In: 'International Journal of Philosophical Studies', vol. 11, pp.25-41.
@

Jackson, F.

(1994): Finding the mind in the natural world. In: R. Casati; B. Smith; S. White (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Cognitive Sciences'. Holder-Pichler-Tempsky.
@

Jackson, F.

(1995): Essentialism, mental properties, and causation. In: ' 1995'.
@

Jackson, F.

(1996): Mental causation. In: 'Mind', vol. 105, pp.377-413.
@

Jackson, F.

(1996): The primary quality view of color. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 10, pp.199-219.
@

Jackson, F.

(1998): Colour, disjunctions, programming. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 58, pp.86-88.
@

Jackson, F.

(1999): All that can be at issue in the theory-theory/simulation debate. In: 'Philosophical Papers', vol. 28, pp.77-96.
@

Jackson, F.

(2001): Locke-ing onto content. In: D. Walsh (Ed.): ' Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Jackson, F.

(2003): Representation and narrow belief. In: ' Philosophical Issues', vol. 13, pp.99-112.
@

Jackson, F.

(2004): Why we need A-intensions. In: '2004'.
@

Jackson, F.; Pargetter, R.

(1987): An objectivist's guide to subjectivism about color . In: 'Revue Internationale de Philosophie', vol. 41.
@

Jackson, F.; Pargetter, R.; Prior, E. W.

(1982): Functionalism and type-type identity theories. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 42, pp.209-25.
@

Jackson, F.; Pettit, P.

(1988): Functionalism and broad content. In: 'Mind ', vol. 97, pp.318-400.
@

Jackson, F.; Pettit, P.

(1990): In defense of folk psychology. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 59, pp.31-54.
@

Jackson, F.; Pettit, P.

(1990): Causation and the philosophy of mind. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Supplement', vol. 50, pp.195-214.
@

Jackson, F.; Pettit, P.

(1990): Program explanation: A general perspective. In: 'Analysis', vol. 50, pp.107-17.
@

Jackson, F.; and Pettit, P.

(1993): Some content is narrow. In: J. Heil and A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Jacob, P.

(1992): Externalism and mental causation. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 66, pp.203-19.
@

Jacob, P.

(1993): Externalism and the explanatory relevance of broad content. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 8.
@

Jacob, P.

(1997): What Minds Can Do: Intentionality in a Non-intentional World. Cambridge University Press.
@

Jacob, P.

(2002): The scope and limit of mental simulation. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Jacobson, A.

(2003): Mental representations: What philosophy leaves out and neuroscience puts in. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 16, pp.189-204.
@

Jacoby, H.

(1985): Eliminativism, meaning and qualitative states. In: '1985 '.
@

Jacovides, M.

(2000): Cambridge changes of color. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 81, pp.142-164.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1985): Logical behaviorism and the simulation of mental episodes. In: 'Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 6, pp.325-332.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1987): Metamathematical criteria for minds and machines. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 27, pp.1-16.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1989): Searle's intentionality thesis. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 80, pp.267-75.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1989): Adventures in the Chinese Room. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 49, pp.605-23.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1990): Intentionality and Stich's theory of brain sentence syntax. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly,', vol. 40, pp.169-82.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1990): Fear and loathing (and other intentional states) in Searle's Chinese Room. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 3, pp.287-304.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1993): Who's afraid of the Turing test?. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.63-74.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1993): A Turing test conversation. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 68, pp.231-33.
@

Jacquette, D.

(1996): Lloyd on intrinsic natural representation in simple mechanical minds . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 6, pp.47-60.
@

Jahren, N.

(1990): Can semantics be syntactic?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 82, pp.309-28.
@

James, W.

(1884): What is an emotion?. In: 'Mind', vol. 19, pp.188-204.
@

Janlert, L.

(1987): Modeling change: The frame problem. In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): ' The Robot's Dilemma'. Ablex.
@

Jaworksi, W.

(2002): Multiple-realizability, explanation, and the disjunctive move. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 108, pp.298-308.
@

Jeannerod, M.; Pacherie, E.

(2004): Agency, simulation and self-identification. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.113-146.
@

Jessor, R.

(1958): The problem of reductionism in psychology. In: ' Psychological Review', vol. 65, pp.170-78.
@

Johannson, I.

(2001): Species and dimensions of pleasure. In: 'Metaphysica ', vol. 2, no.2, pp.39-72.
@

Johnson, K.

(2004): On the systematicity of the language of thought. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 101, pp.111-139.
@

Johnson, K.

(2004): Gold's theorem and cognitive science. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 70.
@

Johnson, M. L.

(1987): The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason. University of Chicago Press.
@

Johnson, M. L.

(1995): Incarnate mind. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp.533-45.
@

Johnson-Laird, P.

(1977): Procedural semantics. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 5, pp.189-214.
@

Johnson-Laird, P.

(1978): What's wrong with Grandma's guide to procedural semantics: A reply to Jerry Fodor. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 9, pp.249-61.
@

Johnston, M.

(1985): Why having a mind matters. In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): 'Action and Events'. Blackwell.
@

Johnston, M.

(1987): Human beings. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 84, pp.59-83.
@

Johnston, M.

(1989): Fission and the facts. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 3, pp.369-97.
@

Johnston, M.

(1992): Reasons and reductionism. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 3, pp.589-618.
@

Johnston, M.

(1992): How to speak of the colors. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 68, pp.221-263.
@

Jones, D. H.

(1972): Emergent properties, persons, and the mind-body problem. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 10, pp.423-33.
@

Jones, J. R.

(1950): Our knowledge of other persons. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 25.
@

Jopling, D. A.

(2000): Self-Knowledge and the Self. Routledge.
@

Jorgensen, J.

(1949): Remarks concerning the concept of mind and the problem of other people's minds. In: '1949'.
@

Joske, W.

(1960): Sensations and brain processes: A reply to Professor Smart. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 38, pp.157-60.
@

Joyce, P.

(2003): Imagining experiences correctly. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 103, pp.361-370.
@

Joyce, R.

(2002): Moral realism and teleosemantics. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 16, pp.723-31.
@

Judson, L.

(1988): Russell on memory. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 88, pp.65-82.

K


@

Kahneman, D.; Slovic, P.; Tversky, A.

(1982): Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge University Press.
@

Kahneman, D.; Tversky, A.

(1979): On the interpretation of intuitive probability: A reply to Jonathan Cohen. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 7, pp.409-11.
@

Kalderon, M. E.

(1987): Epiphenomenalism and content. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 52, pp.71-90.
@

Kalke, W.

(1969): What's wrong with Fodor's and Putnam's functionalism. In: 'Nous', vol. 3, pp.83-93.
@

Kane, R.

(1985): Free Will and Values. SUNY Press.
@

Kane, R.

(1988): Libertarianism and rationality revisited. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 26, pp.441-60.
@

Kane, R.

(1989): Two kinds of incompatibilism. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 69, pp.219-54.
@

Kane, R.

(1994): Free will: The illusive ideal. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 75, pp.25-60.
@

Kane, R.

(1996): The Significance of Free Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Kane, R.

(1996): Free will, responsibility, and will-setting. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 24, pp.67-90.
@

Kane, R.

(1999): Responsibility, luck, and chance: Reflections on free will and determinism . In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 96, pp.217-40.
@

Kane, R.

(2000): The dual regress of free will and the role of alternative possibilities . In: 'Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.57-80.
@

Kane, R.

(2001): Free Will. Blackwell.
@

Kane, R.

(2002): The Oxford Handbook of Free Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Kane, R.

(2002): Some neglected pathways in the free will labyrinth. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Kane, R.

(2002): The contours of contemporary free will debates. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Kane, R.

(2002): The Oxford Handbook on Free Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Kane, R.

(2002): Some neglected pathways in the free will labyrinth. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Kane, R. H.

(1966): Turing machines and mental reports. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 44, pp.344-52.
@

Kapitan, T.

(1986): Deliberation and the presumption of open alternatives. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 40, pp.230-51.
@

Kapitan, T.

(1991): Ability and cognition: A defense of compatibilism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 63, pp.231-43.
@

Kapitan, T.

(1996): Modal principles in the metaphysics of free will. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 10, pp.419-45.
@

Kapitan, T.

(2000): Autonomy and manipulated freedom. In: ' Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.81-104.
@

Kapitan, T.

(2002): A master argument for incompatibilism?. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Kapitan, T.

(2002): A master argument for incompatibilism?. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Kaplan, S.; Weaver, M.; French, R. M.

(1990): Active symbols and internal models: Towards a cognitive connectionism. In: '1990'.
@

Karelis, C.

(1986): Reflections on the Turing test. In: ' Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior', vol. 16, pp.161-72.
@

Katz, J.

(1966): Innate ideas. In: 'The Philosophy of Language'.
@

Katz, J.

(1990): The domino theory. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 58, pp.3-39.
@

Katz, J.

(2000): Realistic Rationalism. MIT Press.
@

Kaufman, R.

(1985): Is the concept of pain incoherent?. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.279-84.
@

Kaye, L. J.

(1993): Are most of our concepts innate?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 2, pp.187-217.
@

Kaye, L. J.

(1994): The computational account of belief. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 40, pp.137-53.
@

Kaye, L. J.

(1995): The languages of thought. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 62, pp.92-110.
@

Kaye, L. J.

(1995): A scientific psychologistic foundation for theories of meaning. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.187-206.
@

Kazez, J. R.

(1994): Computationalism and the causal role of content. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 75, pp.231-60.
@

Kazez, J. R.

(1995): Can counterfactuals save mental causation?. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 73, pp.71-90.
@

Kearns, J. T.

(1997): Thinking machines: Some fundamental confusions. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 7, pp.269-87.
@

Keeley, B.

(1999): Fixing content and function in neurobiological systems: The neuroethology of electroreception. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 14, pp.395-430.
@

Keeley, B.

(1999): Fixing content and function in neurobiological systems: The neuroethology of electroreception. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 14, pp.395-430.
@

Keeley, B.

(2000): Neuroethology and the philosophy of cognitive science. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 60.
@

Keeley, B.

(2000): Neuroethology and the philosophy of cognitive science. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 67, pp.404-418.
@

Keijzer, F. A.

(1998): Doing without representations which specify what to do. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 11, pp.269-302.
@

Keijzer, F. A.; Bem, S.

(1996): Behavioral systems interpreted as autonomous agents and as coupled dynamical systems: A criticism. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 9, pp.323-46.
@

Kekes, J.

(1966): Physicalism, the identity theory, and the concept of emergence. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 33, pp.360-75.
@

Kelly, T.

(2002): The rationality of belief and other propositional attitudes. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 110, pp.163-96.
@

Kemmerling, A.

(1999): How self-knowledge can't be naturalized (some remarks on a proposal by Dretske). In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 95, pp.311-28.
@

Kenny, A.

(1976): Will, Freedom, and Power. Blackwell.
@

Kenny, A.

(1978): Free Will and Responsibility. Routledge.
@

Kenyon, T.

(2000): Indeterminacy and realism. In: A. Brook; D. Ross; D. Thompson (Ed.): 'Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment'. MIT Press.
@

Kernohan, A.

(1985): Psychology: Autonomous or anomalous?. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 24, pp.427-42.
@

Kernohan, A.

(1988): Non-reductive materialism and the spectrum of mind-body identity theories. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 27, pp.475-88.
@

Kernohan, A.

(1990): Lewis's functionalism and reductive materialism. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 3, pp.235-46.
@

Khalidi, M. A.

(1995): Two concepts of concept. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 10, pp.402-22.
@

Khalidi, M. A.

(2001): Innateness and domain-specificity. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 105, pp.191-210.
@

Khalidi, M. A.

(2002): Nature and nurture in cognition. In: ' The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 53, pp.251-272.
@

Killeen, P. R.

(2004): Minding behavior. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 32, pp.125-147.
@

Kim, J.

(1966): On the psycho-physical identity theory. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 3, pp.227-35.
@

Kim, J.

(1972): Phenomenal properties, psychophysical laws and the identity theory. In: 'Monist', vol. 56, pp.178-92.
@

Kim, J.

(1978): Supervenience and nomological incommensurables. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 15, pp.149-56.
@

Kim, J.

(1979): Causality, identity and supervenience in the mind-body problem. In: 'Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 4, pp.31-49.
@

Kim, J.

(1982): Psychophysical supervenience. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 41, pp.51-70.
@

Kim, J.

(1982): Psychophysical supervenience as a mind-body theory. In: ' Cognition and Brain Theory', vol. 5, pp.129-47.
@

Kim, J.

(1984): Concepts of supervenience. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 45, pp.153-76.
@

Kim, J.

(1984): Supervenience and supervenient causation. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 22, pp.45-56.
@

Kim, J.

(1984): Epiphenomenal and supervenient causation. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 9, pp.257-70.
@

Kim, J.

(1985): Psychophysical laws. In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): ' Action and Events'. Blackwell.
@

Kim, J.

(1987): `Strong' and `global' supervenience revisited. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 48, pp.315-26.
@

Kim, J.

(1988): Supervenience for multiple domains. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 16, pp.129-50.
@

Kim, J.

(1989): The myth of non-reductive materialism. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 63, no.3, pp.31-47.
@

Kim, J.

(1989): Mechanism, purpose, and explanatory exclusion. In: ' <i>Philosophical Perspectives</i>', vol. 3, pp.77-108.
@

Kim, J.

(1990): Explanatory exclusion and the problem of mental causation. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Kim, J.

(1991): Supervenience as a philosophical concept. In: ' Metaphilosophy', vol. 21, pp.1-27.
@

Kim, J.

(1992): Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 52, pp.1-26.
@

Kim, J.

(1992): The nonreductivist's trouble with mental causation. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Kim, J.

(1992): "Downward causation" in emergentism and nonreductive physicalism. In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism'. De Gruyter.
@

Kim, J.

(1992): The nonreductivist's trouble with mental causation. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Kim, J.

(1992): "Downward causation" in emergentism and nonreductive physicalism. In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism'. De Gruyter.
@

Kim, J.

(1993): Naturalism and semantic normativity. In: ' Philosophical Issues', vol. 4.
@

Kim, J.

(1993): Supervenience and Mind. Cambridge University Press.
@

Kim, J.

(1993): Can supervenience and "non-strict laws" save anomalous monism?. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Kim, J.

(1993): Mental causation in a physical world. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): ' Science and Knowledge'. Ridgeview.
@

Kim, J.

(1994): `Second-order' properties and mental causation.
@

Kim, J.

(1995): Mental causation: What? Me worry?. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): ' Content'. Ridgeview.
@

Kim, J.

(1996): Philosophy of Mind. Westview Press.
@

Kim, J.

(1997): Supervenience, emergence, and realization in the philosophy of mind. In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind'. Pittsburgh University Press.
@

Kim, J.

(1997): Does the problem of mental causation generalize?. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 97, pp.281-97.
@

Kim, J.

(1999): Making sense of emergence. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 95, pp.3-36.
@

Kim, J.

(1999): Supervenient properties and micro-based concepts: A reply to Noordhof . In: 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 99, pp.115-118.
@

Kim, J.

(2000): Mind in a Physical World: An Essay on the Mind-Body Problem and Mental Causation. MIT Press.
@

Kim, J.

(2002): Horgan's naturalistic metaphysics of mind. In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 63, pp.27-52.
@

Kim, J.

(2003): Chisholm's legacy on intentionality. In: 'Metaphilosophy ', vol. 34, pp.649-662.
@

Kim, J.

(2003): Lonely souls: Causality and substance dualism. In: T. O'Connor; D. Robb; (eds (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings'. Routledge.
@

Kim, J.

(2003): Blocking causal drainage and other maintenance chores with mental causation . In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 67, pp.151-176.
@

Kim, J.

(2005): Physicalism, or Something Near Enough. Princeton University Press.
@

Kim, S.

(2002): Testing multiple realizability: A discussion of Bechtel and Mundale. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 69, pp.606-610.
@

Kincaid, H.

(1987): Supervenience doesn't entail reducibility. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 25, pp.343-56.
@

Kincaid, H.

(1988): Supervenience and explanation. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 77, pp.251-81.
@

Kind, A.

(2001): Putting the image back in imagination. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 62, pp.85-110.
@

King, D.

(1996): Is the human mind a Turing machine?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 108, pp.379-89.
@

King, D.

(2001): Entering the Chinese room with Castaneda's principle (p). In: 'Philosophy Today', vol. 45, pp.168-174.
@

Kirk, R.

(1979): From physical explicability to full-blooded materialism. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 29, pp.229-37.
@

Kirk, R.

(1982): Physicalism, identity, and strict implication. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 24, pp.131-41.
@

Kirk, R.

(1986): Mental machinery and Godel. In: '1986'.
@

Kirk, R.

(1986): Sentience, causation and some robots. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 64, pp.308-21.
@

Kirk, R.

(1996): Strict implication, supervenience, and physicalism. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 74, pp.244-57.
@

Kirk, R.

(1996): How physicalists can avoid reductionism. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 108, pp.157-70.
@

Kirk, R.

(1996): Physicalism lives. In: 'Ratio', vol. 9, pp.85-89.
@

Kirk, R.

(2001): Nonreductive physicalism and strict implication. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 79, pp.544-552.
@

Kirsh, D.

(1987): Putting a price on cognition. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 26, pp.119-35.
@

Kirsh, D.

(1990): When is information explicitly represented?. In: P. Hanson (Ed.): 'Information, Language and Cognition'. University of British Columbia Press.
@

Kirsh, D.

(1991): Today the earwig, tomorrow man?. In: ' Artificial Intelligence', vol. 47, pp.161-184.
@

Kirsh, D.

(1991): Foundations of AI: The big issues. In: ' Artificial Intelligence', vol. 47, pp.3-30.
@

Kirsh, D.; Maglio, P.

(1995): On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action. In: 'Cognitive Science', vol. 18, pp.513-49.
@

Kistler, M.

(1999): Multiple realization, reduction and mental properties. In: 'International Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 13.
@

Kistler, M.

(2000): Source and channel in the informational theory of mental content . In: 'Facta Philosophica', vol. 2, pp.213-36.
@

Kitamura, T.

(2002): What is the self of a robot? On a consciousness architecture for a mobile robot as a model of human consciousness . In: K. Yasue; M. Jibu; T. Senta (Ed.): 'No Matter, Never Mind'. John Benjamins.
@

Kitamura, T.; Tahara, T.; Asami, K.

(2000): How can a robot have consciousness?. In: 'Advanced Robotics', vol. 14, pp.263-275.
@

Kitchener, R. F.

(1977): Behavior and behaviorism. In: 'Behaviorism ', vol. 5, pp.11-68.
@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1980): How to reduce a functional psychology. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 47, pp.134-40.
@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1982): Two versions of the identity theory. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 17, pp.213-28.
@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1984): In defense of intentional psychology. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 81, pp.89-106.
@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1984): Narrow taxonomy and wide functionalism. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 52, pp.78-97.
@

Kitcher, P. S.

(1988): Marr's computational theory of vision. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 55, pp.1-24.
@

Klagge, J. C.

(1988): Supervenience: Ontological and ascriptive. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 66, pp.461-70.
@

Klagge, J. C.

(1989): Wittgenstein and neuroscience. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 78, pp.319-43.
@

Klagge, J. C.

(1990): Davidson's troubles with supervenience. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 85, pp.339-52.
@

Klagge, J. C.

(1995): Supervenience: Model theory or metaphysics?. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Klee, J.

(1984): Microdeterminism and concepts of emergence. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 51, pp.44-63.
@

Klee, R.

(1992): Anomalous monism, ceteris paribus, and psychological explanation. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 43, pp.389-403.
@

Klee, R.

(2004): Why some delusions are necessarily inexplicable beliefs. In: 'Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 11, pp.25-34.
@

Klein, M.

(1990): Determinism, blameworthiness, and deprivation. In: '1990 '.
@

Klein, M.

(1996): Externalism, content, and causation. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 96, pp.159-76.
@

Kliewer, G.

(1998): Neutral color concepts. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 91, pp.21-41.
@

Knight, D.

(1997): A poetics of psychological explanation. In: ' Metaphilosophy', vol. 28, pp.63-80.
@

Knobe, J.

(2003): Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 16, pp.309-325.
@

Knowles, J.

(1998): The language of thought and natural language understanding. In: 'Analysis', vol. 58, pp.264-272.
@

Knowles, J.

(1999): Physicalism, teleology and the miraculous coincidence problem. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.164-81.
@

Knowles, J.

(2002): Is folk psychology different?. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 57, pp.199-230.
@

Kober, M.

(1998): Kripkenstein meets the Chinese room: Looking for the place of meaning from a natural point of view. In: 'Inquiry', vol. 41, pp.317-332.
@

Kobes, B.

(1989): Semantics and psychological prototypes. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 70, pp.1-18.
@

Kobes, B.

(1990): Individualism and artificial intelligence. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 4, pp.429-56.
@

Kobes, B.

(1991): On a model for psycho-neural coevolution. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.1-17.
@

Kobes, B.

(1996): Mental content and hot self-knowledge. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 24, pp.71-99.
@

Kobes, B.

(2003): Mental content and hot self-knowledge. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Koethe, J.

(1992): And they ain't outside the head either. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 90, pp.27-53.
@

Kolak, D.

(1993): The metaphysics and metapsychology of personal identity: Why thought experiments matter in deciding who we are. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 30, pp.39-50.
@

Kolak, D.

(1993): Finding our selves: Identification, identity, and multiple personality . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 6, pp.363-86.
@

Kolak, D.; Martin, R.

(1987): Personal identity and causality: Becoming unglued. In: '1987'.
@

Kolak, D.; Martin, R.

(1991): Self and Identity: Contemporary Philosophical Issues. Macmillan.
@

Koons, R.

(2002): Is hard determinism a form of compatibilism?. In: ' Philosophical Forum', vol. 33, pp.81-99.
@

Korb, K.

(1991): Searle's AI program. In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 3, pp.283-96.
@

Korb, K.

(1998): The frame problem: An AI fairy tale. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 8, pp.317-351.
@

Korsgaard, C.

(1989): Personal identity and the unity of agency: A Kantian response to Parfit. In: ' Philosophy and Public Affairs', vol. 18, pp.103-31.
@

Kosslyn, S. M.

(1980): Image and Mind. Harvard University Press.
@

Kosslyn, S. M.

(1981): The medium and the message in mental imagery: A theory. In: N. Block (Ed.): 'Imagery'. MIT Press.
@

Kosslyn, S. M.

(1994): Image and Brain: The Resolution of the Imagery Debate. MIT Press.
@

Kosslyn, S. M.; Hatfield, G.

(1984): Representation without symbol systems. In: 'Social Research', vol. 51, pp.1019-1045.
@

Kosslyn, S. M.; Pinker, S.; Schwartz, S.; Smith, G.

(1979): On the demystification of mental imagery. In: 'Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 2, pp.535-81.
@

Kosslyn, S. M.; Pomerantz, J.

(1977): Imagery, propositions and the form of internal representations. In: 'Cognitive Psychology ', vol. 9, pp.52-76.
@

Kovach, A.; De Lancey, C.

(2005): On emotions and the explanation of behavior. In: 'Nous', vol. 39, pp.106-22.
@

Kraay, K. J.

(2002): Externalism, memory, and self-knowledge. In: ' Erkenntnis', vol. 56, pp.297-317.
@

Kraut, R.

(1992): The objectivity of color and the color of objectivity. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 3, pp.265-87.
@

Krebs, V.

(1986): Objectivity and meaning: Wittgenstein on following rules. In: 'Philosophical Investigations', vol. 9, pp.177-186.
@

Krellenstein, M.

(1987): A reply to `Parallel computation and the mind-body problem' . In: 'Cognitive Science', vol. 11, pp.155-7.
@

Kremer, M.

(2000): Wilson on Kripke's Wittgenstein. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 60, pp.571-584.
@

Kriegel, U.

(2002): Emotional content. In: 'Consciousness and Emotion ', vol. 3, pp.213-230.
@

Kuczynski, J. M.

(1998): A proof of the partial anomalousness of the mental. In: 'Southern Journal Of Philosophy', vol. 36, pp.491-504.
@

Kugel, P.

(2002): Computing machines can't be intelligent (...and Turing said so). In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 12, pp.563-579.
@

Kuhberger, A, Perner, J.; Schulte, M.; Leingruber, R.

(1995): Choice or no choice: Is the Langer effect evidence against simulation?. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 10, pp.423-36.
@

Kukla, A.

(1989): Is AI an empirical science?. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 49, pp.56-60.
@

Kukla, A.

(1989): Non-empirical issues in psychology. In: ' American Psychologist', vol. 44, pp.485-94.
@

Kukla, A.

(1994): Medium AI and experimental science. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.493-5012.
@

Kukla, A.; Kukla, R.

(1989): Meaning holism and intentional psychology. In: 'Analysis', vol. 173.
@

Kukla, R.

(1992): Cognitive models and representation. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 43, pp.219-32.
@

Kukla, R.

(2000): How to get an interpretivist committed. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 14, pp.180-221.
@

Kulvicki, J.

(2004): Isomorphism in information-carrying systems. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 85.
@

Kurthen, M. Moskopp, D.; Linke, D. B.; Reuter, B. M.

(1991): The locked-in syndrome and the behaviorist epistemology of other minds. In: 'Theoretical Medicine ', vol. 12, pp.69-79.
@

Kurtzman, H. S.

(1983): Modern conceptions of memory. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 44, pp.1-20.
@

Kusch, M.

(2005): Fodor v. Kripke: Semantic dispositionalism, idealization, and ceteris paribus clauses. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 65, pp.156-63.
@

Kvart, I.

(1986): Beliefs and believing. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 52, pp.129-45.

L


@

Laakso, A.; Cottrell, G.

(2000): Content and cluster analysis: assessing representational similarity in neural systems. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.47-76.
@

Lacey, N.; Lee, M.

(2003): The epistemological foundations of artificial agents. Minds and Machines 13:339-365. Lee, M. & Lacey, N. 2003. The influence of epistemology on the design of artificial agents . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 13, pp.367-395.
@

Lachter, J.; Bever, T.

(1988): The relation between linguistic structure and associative theories of language learning. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 28, pp.195-247.
@

Lackey, J.

(2002): Explanation and mental causation. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 40.
@

Ladd, J.

(1952): Free will and voluntary action. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 12, pp.392-405.
@

Lahav, R.

(1991): Between pre-determinism and arbitrariness: A Bergsonian approach to free will. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 29, pp.487-99.
@

Lahav, R.

(1992): The amazing predictive power of folk psychology. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 70, pp.99-105.
@

Lalor, B. J.

(1997): It is what you think: intentional potency and anti-individualism . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 10, pp.165-78.
@

Lalor, B. J.

(1998): Swampman, etiology, and content. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 36, pp.215-232.
@

Lamb, J. W.

(1977): On a proof of incompatibilism. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 86, pp.20-35.
@

Lamb, J. W.

(1993): Evaluative compatibilism and the principle of alternate possibilities . In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 90, pp.517-27.
@

Lance, M.; O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.

(1997): The Grammar of Meaning. Cambridge University Press.
@

Landers, S.

(1990): Wittgenstein, realism, and CLS: Undermining rule scepticism. In: 'Law and Philosophy', vol. 9, pp.177-203.
@

Landesman, C.

(1964): Dreams: Two types of explanation. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 15, pp.17-23.
@

Landesman, C.

(1989): Color and Consciousness: An Essay in Metaphysics. Temple University Press.
@

Langdon, R.; Coltheart, M.

(2000): The cognitive neuropsychology of delusions. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 15, pp.183-216.
@

Langsam, H.

(1995): Why pains are mental objects. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 6, pp.303-13.
@

Langsam, H.

(2000): Why colours do look like dispositions. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 50, pp.68-75.
@

Langsam, H.

(2001): Strategy for dualists. In: 'Metaphilosophy ', vol. 32, pp.395-418.
@

Langsam, H.

(2001): Pain, personal identity, and the deep further fact. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 54, pp.247-271.
@

Langsam, H.

(2002): Externalism, self-knowledge, and inner observation. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 80, pp.42-61.
@

Lanier, J.

(1998): Three objections to the idea of artificial intelligence. In: S. Hameroff; A. Kaszniak; A. Scott (Ed.): 'Toward a Science of Consciousness II'. MIT Press.
@

Larkin, W. S.

(1999): Brute error with respect to content. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 94, pp.159-71.
@

Larkin, W. S.

(1999): Shoemaker on Moore's paradox and self-knowledge. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 96, pp.239-52.
@

Larmer, R.

(1986): Mind-body interactionism and the conservation of energy. In: 'International Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 26, pp.277-85.
@

Larson, E.

(1994): Needs versus desires. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 37, pp.1-10.
@

Latham, N.

(1999): Davidson and Kim on psychophysical laws. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 118, pp.121-44.
@

Latham, N.

(2001): Substance physicalism. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): ' Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Lau, J.

(2002): Externalism about mental content. In: '2002'.
@

Laurence, S.; Margolis, E.

(1997): Regress arguments for the language of thought. In: 'Analysis', vol. 57, pp.60-66.
@

Laurence, S.; Margolis, E.

(2001): The poverty of the stimulus argument. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 52, pp.217-276.
@

Laurence, S.; Margolis, E.

(2003): Concepts and conceptual analysis. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 67, pp.253-282.
@

Laurence, S.; Margolis, E.

(2003): Radical concept nativism. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 86, pp.25-55.
@

Lawlor, K.

(2002): Memory, anaphora, and content preservation. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 109, pp.97-119.
@

Lawlor, K.

(2003): Elusive reasons: A problem for first-person authority. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 16, pp.549-565.
@

Lawlor, K.

(2004): Reason and the past: The role of rationality in diachronic self-knowledge . In: '2004'.
@

LeBar, M.

(2001): Simulation, theory, and emotion. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.423-434.
@

LePore, E.

(1990): Subjectivism and environmentalism. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 33, pp.197-214.
@

LePore, E.; Loewer, B.

(1986): Solipsistic semantics. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 10, pp.595-614.
@

LePore, E.; Loewer, B.

(1987): Mind matters. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 630.
@

LePore, E.; Loewer, B.

(1989): Dual aspect semantics. In: S. Silvers (Ed.): ' ReRepresentation'. Kluwer.
@

LePore, E.; Loewer, B.

(1989): More on making mind matter. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 17, pp.175-91.
@

Leder, D.

(1985): Troubles with token identity. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 47, pp.79-94.
@

Lee, B.

(2002): Shoemaker on second-order belief and self-deception. In: ' Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review', vol. 41.
@

Lee, E. T.

(1996): On the Turing test for artificial intelligence. In: ' Kybernetes', vol. 25.
@

Lee, W.

(1990): Personal identity, the temporality of agency, and moral responsibility . In: 'Auslegung', vol. 16, pp.17-29.
@

Legg, C. R.

(1988): Connectionism and physiological psychology: A marriage made in heaven? . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 1, pp.263-78.
@

Lehrer, K.

(1964): 'Could' and determinism. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 24, pp.159-60.
@

Lehrer, K.

(1966): Freedom and Determinism. Random House.
@

Lehrer, K.

(1966): An empirical disproof of determinism. In: K. Lehrer (Ed.): ' Freedom and Determinism'. Random House.
@

Lehrer, K.

(1976): 'Can' in theory and practice: A possible worlds analysis. In: M. Brand; D. Walton (Ed.): 'Action Theory'. Reidel.
@

Lehrer, K.

(1983): Belief, acceptance, and cognition. In: H. Parret (Ed.): ' On Believing'. De Gruyter.
@

Lehrer, K.

(1986): Metamind: Belief, consciousness and intentionality. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Belief: Form, Content, and Function'. Oxford University Press.
@

Leiber, J.

(1989): Shanon on the Turing test. In: '1989'.
@

Leiber, J.

(1995): On Turing's Turing Test and why the matter matters. In: ' Synthese', vol. 104, pp.59-69.
@

Leiber, J.

(2001): Turing and the fragility and insubstantiality of evolutionary explanations: A puzzle about the unity of Alan Turing's work with some larger implications . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.83-94.
@

Leiter, B.; Miller, A.

(1994): Mind doesn't matter yet. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 72, pp.220-28.
@

Leiter, B.; Miller, A.

(1998): Closet dualism and mental causation. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 28, pp.161-181.
@

Lemaire, S.

(2002): From emotions to desires. In: ' European Review of Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.109-136.
@

Lenman, J.

(1994): Beliefs about other minds: A pragmatic justification. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 31, pp.223-34.
@

Leon, M.

(1998): The unnaturalness of the mental: The status of folk psychology. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 36, pp.367-92.
@

Leon, M.

(2002): Colour wars: Dividing the spoils. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp.175-192.
@

Leslie, A. M.; German, T. P.

(1995): Knowledge and ability in "theory of mind": A one-eyed overview of a debate. In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): ' Mental Simulation'. Blackwell.
@

Letwin, O.

(1987): Ethics, Emotion, and the Unity of the Self. Croom Helm.
@

Levi, I.

(2002): Commitment and change of view. In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature'. Clarendon.
@

Levin, J.

(1995): Folk psychology and the simulationist challenge. In: ' Acta Analytica', vol. 10, pp.77-100.
@

Levin, J.

(2000): Dispositional theories of color and the claims of common sense. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 100, pp.151-174.
@

Levin, M.

(1984): Why we believe in other minds. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 44, pp.343-59.
@

Levine, A.; Bickhard, MH.

(1999): Concepts: Where Fodor went wrong. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 12, pp.5-23.
@

Levine, J.

(1996): Swampjoe: mind or simulation?. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp.86-91.
@

Levy, D.

(2003): Neural holism and free will. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 16, pp.205-229.
@

Levy, K.

(2001): The main problem with USC libertarianism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 105, pp.107-127.
@

Levy, N.

(2004): Evolutionary psychology, human universals, and the standard social science model. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.459-72.
@

Lewis, A.

(1988): Wittgenstein and rule-scepticism. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 38, pp.280-304.
@

Lewis, D.

(1965): An argument for the identity theory. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 63, pp.17-25.
@

Lewis, D.

(1966): An argument for the identity theory. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 63, pp.17-25.
@

Lewis, D.

(1969): Lucas against mechanism. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 44, pp.231-3.
@

Lewis, D.

(1972): Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 50, pp.249-58.
@

Lewis, D.

(1972): Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 50, pp.249-58.
@

Lewis, D.

(1976): Survival and identity. In: A. Rorty (Ed.): ' The Identities of Persons'. University of California Press.
@

Lewis, D.

(1978): Mad pain and martian pain. In: N. Block (Ed.): ' Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology'. @

Lewis, D.

(1979): Lucas against mechanism II. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 9, pp.373-6.
@

Lewis, D.

(1981): Are we free to break the laws?. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 47, pp.113-21.
@

Lewis, D.

(1983): New work for a theory of universals. In: '1983'.
@

Lewis, D.

(1988): Desire as belief. In: 'Mind', vol. 97, pp.323-32.
@

Lewis, D.

(1996): Desire as belief II. In: 'Mind', vol. 105, pp.303-13.
@

Lewis, D.

(1997): Naming the colours. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 75, pp.325-42.
@

Lewis, H.

(1985): Is the mental supervenient on the physical?. In: B. Vermazen; M. Hintikka (Ed.): 'Essays on Davidson'. Oxford University Press.
@

Libet, B.

(1999): Do we have free will?. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 6, pp.47-57.
@

Libet, B.

(2001): Consciousness, free action and the brain: Commentary on John Searle's article (with reply from Searle). In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 8, pp.59-65.
@

Libet, B.

(2002): Do we have free will?. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Libet, B.; Freeman, A.; Sutherland, K.

(1999): The Volitional Brain: Towards a Neuroscience of Free Will. Imprint Academic.
@

Lidz, J.; Waxman, S.

(2004): Reaffirming the poverty of the stimulus argument: A reply to the replies. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 93, pp.157-165.
@

Litch, M.

(1997): Computation, connectionism and modelling the mind. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 10, pp.357-364.
@

Livet, P.

(2002): Emotions, revision, and the explanation of actions. In: ' European Review of Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.93-108.
@

Livingston, K. R.

(1989): Concepts, categories, and epistemology. In: ' Philosophia', vol. 19, pp.265-300.
@

Liz, M.

(2003): Intentional states: Individuation, explanation, and supervenience. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Lizza, J. P.

(1993): Multiple personality and personal identity revisited. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 44, pp.263-274.
@

Lloyd, D.

(1987): Mental representation from the bottom up. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 70, pp.23-78.
@

Lloyd, D.

(1989): Parallel distributed processing and cognition: Only connect?. In: 'Simple Minds'.
@

Lloyd, D.

(1989): Simple Minds. MIT Press.
@

Lloyd, D.

(2000): Terra cognita: From functional neuroimaging to the map of the mind . In: 'Brain and Mind', vol. 1, pp.93-116.
@

Lloyd, D.

(2002): Studying the mind from the inside out. In: 'Brain and Mind ', vol. 3, pp.243-59.
@

Lloyd, E.

(2004): Kanzi, evolution, and language. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.577-88.
@

Lloyd, E. A.

(1999): Evolutionary psychology: The burdens or proof. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 14, pp.211-33.
@

Loar, B.

(1982): Must beliefs be sentences?. In: '1982'.
@

Loar, B.

(1982): Conceptual role and truth conditions. In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic', vol. 23, pp.272-83.
@

Loar, B.

(1987): Social content and psychological content. In: R. Grimm; D. Merrill (Ed.): 'Contents of Thought'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Loar, B.

(1987): Subjective intentionality. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 15, pp.89-124.
@

Loar, B.

(1991): Can we explain intentionality?. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): ' Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Loar, B.

(1992): Elimination versus nonreductive physicalism. In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism'. Oxford University Press.
@

Loar, B.

(1993): Can we confirm supervenient properties?. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Naturalism and Normativity'. Ridgeview.
@

Locke, D.

(1968): Myself and Others: A Study in our Knowledge of Minds. Oxford University Press.
@

Locke, D.

(1971): Must a materialist pretend he's anaesthetized?. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.217-31.
@

Locke, D.

(1971): Memory. Macmillan.
@

Locke, D.

(1973): Just what is wrong with the argument from analogy?. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 51, pp.153-56.
@

Locke, D.

(1975): Three concepts of free action. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 75, pp.95-112.
@

Lockie, R.

(2003): Transcendental arguments against eliminativism. In: ' The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 54, pp.569-589.
@

Lockwood, M.

(1984): Einstein and the identity theory. In: '1984'.
@

Loeffler, R.

(2005): Normative phenomenalism: On Robert Brandom's practice-based explanation of meaning. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 13, pp.32-69.
@

Loewer B.

(1982): The role of `Conceptual role semantics'. In: ' Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic', vol. 23, pp.305-15.
@

Loewer, B.

(1987): From information to intentionality. In: '1987'.
@

Loewer, B.

(1995): An argument for strong supervenience. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Loewer, B.

(1996): Freedom from physics: Quantum mechanics and free will. In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 24, pp.91-112.
@

Loewer, B.

(2001): From physics to physicalism. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Longworth, G.

(2003): Where should we look for the mind?. In: 'Think ', vol. 5.
@

Loren, L. A.; Dietrich, E.

(1997): Merleau-Ponty, embodied cognition, and the problem of intentionality. In: 'Cybernetics and Systems ', vol. 28, pp.345-58.
@

Lormand, E.

(1985): Toward a theory of moods. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 47, pp.385-407.
@

Lormand, E.

(1990): Framing the frame problem. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 82, pp.353-74.
@

Lormand, E.

(1994): The holorobophobe's dilemma. In: K. Ford; Z. Pylylshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma Revisited'. Ablex.
@

Lormand, E.

(1996): How to be a meaning holist. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 93, pp.51-73.
@

Losonsky, M.

(1995): Emdedded systems vs. individualism. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.357-71.
@

Losonsky, M.

(1995): Emdedded systems vs. individualism. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.357-71.
@

Lovejoy, A. O.

(1927): The meanings of "emergence" and its modes. In: E. S. Brightman (Ed.): 'Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Philosophy'. Longmans, Green, and Co.
@

Lowe, E.

(2001): Event causation and agent causation. In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 61, pp.1-20.
@

Lowe, E.

(2002): The rational and the real: Some doubts about the programme of 'Rational analysis'. In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature'. Clarendon.
@

Lowe, E. J.

(1991): Real selves: Persons as a substantial kind. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 29, pp.87-107.
@

Lowe, E. J.

(1992): The problem of psychophysical causation. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 70, pp.263-76.
@

Lowe, E. J.

(1993): The causal autonomy of the mental. In: 'Mind ', vol. 102, pp.629-44.
@

Lowe, E. J.

(2000): Causal closure principles and emergentism. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 75, pp.571-586.
@

Lowe, E. J.

(2000): An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge University Press.
@

Lowe, E. J.

(2003): Physical causal closure and the invisibility of mental causation . In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Lowry, A.

(1974): A note on emergence. In: 'Mind', vol. 83, pp.276-77.
@

Lubow, N.

(1978): Mind-body identity and irreducible properties. In: ' Philosophy Research Archives', vol. 4.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1961): Minds, machines and Godel. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 36, pp.112-127.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1967): Human and machine logic: a rejoinder. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 19, pp.155-6.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1968): Satan stultified: A rejoinder to Paul Benacerraf. In: ' Monist', vol. 52, pp.145-58.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1970): The Freedom of the Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1970): Mechanism: A rejoinder. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 45, pp.149-51.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1970): The Freedom of the Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1971): Metamathematics and the philosophy of mind: A rejoinder. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 38, pp.310-13.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1976): This Godel is killing me: A rejoinder. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 6, pp.145-8.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1984): Lucas against mechanism II: A rejoinder. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 14, pp.189-91.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1994): A view of one's own (conscious machines). In: ' Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, Series A', vol. 349, pp.147-52.
@

Lucas, J. R.

(1996): Mind, machines and Godel: A retrospect. In: P. Millican; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Machines and Thought'. Oxford University Press.
@

Luce, D. R.

(1966): Mind-body identity and psycho-physical correlation. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 17, pp.1-7.
@

Ludlow, P.

(1995): Externalism, self-knowledge, and the prevalence of slow-switching . In: 'Analysis', vol. 55, pp.45-49.
@

Ludlow, P.

(1995): Social externalism, self-knowledge, and memory. In: ' Analysis', vol. 55, pp.157-59.
@

Ludlow, P.

(1995): Social externalism and memory: A problem?. In: ' Acta Analytica', vol. 10, pp.69-76.
@

Ludlow, P.

(1997): On the relevance of slow switching. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 57, pp.285-86.
@

Ludlow, P.; Martin, N.

(1998): Externalism and Self-Knowledge. CSLI.
@

Ludwig, K.

(1993): Externalism, naturalism, and method. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Naturalism and Normativity'. Ridgeview.
@

Ludwig, K.

(1993): Causal relevance and thought content. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 44, pp.334-53.
@

Ludwig, K.

(1996): Duplicating thoughts. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp.92-102.
@

Ludwig, P.

(2002): Reply to 'Can 'radical' simulation theories explain psychological concept acquisition?' In (J. Dokic & J. Proust, eds) Simulation and Knowledge of Action . In: '2002'.
@

Lurie, Y.

(1978): Correlating brain states with psychological phenomena. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 56, pp.135-44.
@

Lycan W. G.

(1999): Dretske on the mind's awareness of itself. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 95, pp.125-33.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1974): Mental states and Putnam's functionalist hypothesis. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 52, pp.48-62.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1976): Quine's materialism. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 6, pp.101-30.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1979): A New Lilliputian argument against machine functionalism. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 35, pp.279-87.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1981): Form, function and feel. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 78, pp.24-50.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1981): Psychological laws. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 12, pp.9-38.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1981): Psychological laws. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 12, pp.9-38.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1982): Toward a homuncular theory of believing. In: ' Cognition and Brain Theory', vol. 4, pp.139-59.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1983): The moral of the New Lilliputian argument. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 43, pp.277-80.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1986): Tacit belief. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): ' Belief: Form, Content, and Function'. Oxford University Press.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1986): Thoughts about things. In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): ' The Representation of Knowledge and Belief'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1989): Ideas of representation. In: Weissbord (Ed.): ' Mind, Value and Culture: Essays in Honor of E. M. Adams'. Ridgeview.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1990): Mental content in linguistic form. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 58, pp.147-54.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1991): Homuncular functionalism meets PDP. In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1993): A deductive argument for the representational theory of thinking . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 8, pp.404-22.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1997): Folk psychology and its liabilities. In: M. Carrier; P. Machamer (Ed.): 'Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind'. Pittsburgh University Press.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(1998): Qualitative experience in machines. In: T. Bynum; J. Moor (Ed.): 'How Computers are Changing Philosophy'. Blackwell.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(2002): Dretske's ways of introspecting. In: B. Gertler (Ed.): ' Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge'. Ashgate.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(2002): Mind and Cognition: An Anthology, 2nd edition. Blackwell.
@

Lycan, W. G.

(2003): Free will and the burden of proof. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Minds and Persons'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Lycan, W. G.; Pappas, G.

(1972): What is eliminative materialism?. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 50, pp.149-59.
@

Lynch, M.; Glasgow, J.

(2003): The impossibility of superdupervenience. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 113, pp.201-221.
@

Lyngzeidetson, A.

(1990): Massively parallel distributed processing and a computationalist foundation for cognitive science. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 41.
@

Lyngzeidetson, A. E.; Solomon, M. K.

(1994): Abstract complexity theory and the mind-machine problem. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 45, pp.549-54.
@

Lyons, W.

(1978): Emotions and behavior. In: '1978'.
@

Lyons, W.

(1980): Emotion. Cambridge University Press.
@

Lyons, W.

(1990): Intentionality and modern philosophical psychology, I. The modern reduction of intentionality. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 3, pp.247-69.

M


@

MacDonald, C.

(1999): Shoemaker on self-knowledge and inner sense. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 59, pp.711-38.
@

MacDorman, K. F.

(1997): How to ground symbols adaptively. In: S. O'Nuillain; P. McKevitt; E. MacAogain (Ed.): 'Two Sciences of Mind'. John Benjamins.
@

MacKay, D. M.

(1967): Freedom of Action in a Mechanistic Universe. Cambridge University Press.
@

MacLennan, B.

(1994): "Words lie in our way". In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 4, pp.421-37.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1989): Mind-Body Identity Theories. Routledge.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1990): Weak externalism and mind-body identity. In: 'Mind ', vol. 99, pp.387-404.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1992): Weak externalism and psychological reduction. In: D Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism'. Oxford University Press.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1992): Psychological type-type reduction via disjunction. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 30, pp.65-69.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1995): Externalism and first-person authority. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 104, pp.99-122.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1995): Psychophysical supervenience, dependency, and reduction. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1995): Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation. Blackwell.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1998): Externalism and authoritative self-knowledge. In: C. Wright; P. Smith; C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Macdonald, C.

(1998): Externalism and norms. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Macdonald, C.

(2002): Theories of mind and 'The commonsense view'. Mind and Language 17:467-488. Maibom, H. 2003. The mindreader and the scientist . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 18, pp.296-315.
@

Macdonald, C.; Macdonald, G.

(1986): Mental causes and explanation of action. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 36, pp.145-58.
@

Macdonald, C.; Macdonald, G.

(1991): Mental causation and nonreductive monism. In: 'Analysis', vol. 51, pp.23-32.
@

Macdonald, C.; Macdonald, G.

(1995): How to be psychologically relevant. In: C. Macdonald; G. Macdonald (Ed.): 'Philosophy of Psychology: Debates on Psychological Explanation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Macdonald, C.; Smith, P.; Wright, C.

(1998): Knowing Our Own Minds: Essays in Self-Knowledge . Oxford University Press.
@

Macdonald, G.

(1989): Biology and representation. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 4, pp.186-200.
@

Macdonald, G.

(1992): The nature of naturalism. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 66, pp.225-44.
@

Mace, C. A.

(1949): Some implications of analytical behaviourism. In: '1949 '.
@

Mace, C. A.

(1949): Causal laws in psychology. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 23, pp.61-68.
@

Machamer, P.; McLaughlin, P.; Grush, R.

(2001): Theory and Method in the Neurosciences . University of Pittsburgh Press.
@

Machina, K.

(1994): Challenges for compatibilism. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 31, pp.213-22.
@

Mackay, D. M.

(1951): Mind-life behavior in artifacts. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 2, pp.105-21.
@

Mackay, D. M.

(1952): Mentality in machines. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 26, pp.61-86.
@

Mackenzie, W. L.

(1926): The notion of emergence. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 6, pp.56-68.
@

Mackie, D.

(1999): Animalism vs. Lockeanism: No contest. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.369-76.
@

Mackie, D.

(1999): Personal identity and dead people. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 95, pp.219-42.
@

Mackie, J. L.

(1963): Are there any incorrigible empirical statements?. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 41, pp.12-28.
@

Mackie, P.

(2003): Fatalism, incompatibilism, and the power to do otherwise. In: 'Nous', vol. 37, pp.672-689.
@

Maclachlan, D. L. C.

(1993): Strawson and the argument for other minds. In: 'Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 18, pp.149-157.
@

Maclennan, B.

(2003): Transcending Turing computability. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 13, pp.3-22.
@

Maddy, P.

(1979): Is the importance of identity derivative?. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 35, pp.151-70.
@

Maddy, P.

(1986): Mathematical alchemy. In: ' British Journal of Philosophy of Science', vol. 46, pp.555-575.
@

Madell, G.

(1981): The Identity of the Self. Edinburgh University Press.
@

Madell, G.

(1985): Derek Parfit and Greta Garbo. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 45, pp.105-9.
@

Madell, G.

(1986): Neurophilosophy: A principled skeptic's response. In: ' 1986'.
@

Madell, G.

(1988): Mind and Materialism. Edinburgh University Press.
@

Madell, G.

(1989): Physicalism and the content of thought. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 32, pp.107-21.
@

Madell, G.

(1991): Personal identity and the idea of a human being. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 29, pp.127-142.
@

Magill, K.

(1997): Experience and Freedom: Self-Determination without Illusions. Macmillan.
@

Maher, B.

(1999): Anomalous experience in everyday life: Its significance for psychopathology. In: 'Monist ', vol. 82, pp.547-70.
@

Maher, B.

(2003): Schizophrenia, aberrant utterance and delusions of control: The disconnection of speech and thought, and the connection of experience and belief . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 18, pp.1-22.
@

Maibom, H. L.

(2005): Moral unreason: The case of psychopathy. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 20, pp.237-57.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1954): Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 43, pp.530-9.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1958): Knowledge of other minds. In: '1958'.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1962): Dreaming. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1963): A definition of factual memory. In: ' Knowledge and Certainty'.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1964): Scientific materialism and the identity theory. In: ' Dialogue', vol. 3, pp.115-25.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1964): Scientific materialism and the identity theory. In: ' 1964'.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1968): The conceivability of mechanism. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 77, pp.45-72.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1970): Memory and representation. In: 'Nous ', vol. 4, pp.59-71.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1973): Thoughtless brutes. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 46, pp.5-20.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1977): Memory and Mind. Cornell University Press.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1980): `Functionalism' in philosophical psychology. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 80, pp.211-30.
@

Malcolm, N.

(1989): Wittgenstein on language and rules. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 64.
@

Malle, B.

(2004): How the Mind Explains Behavior: Folk Explanations, Meaning, and Social Interaction. MIT Press.
@

Maloney, C.

(2001): Reservations about new wave reduction. In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 61, pp.263-277.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1984): Mental images and cognitive theory. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 21, pp.237-47.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1985): Methodological solipsism reconsidered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 52, pp.451-69.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1987): The right stuff. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 70, pp.349-72.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1988): In praise of narrow minds. In: J. Fetzer (Ed.): ' Aspects of AI'. D.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1989): The Mundane Matter of the Mental Language. Cambridge University Press.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1990): It's hard to believe. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 5, pp.122-48.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1990): Mental misrepresentation. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 57, pp.445-58.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1991): Saving psychological solipsism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 61, pp.267-83.
@

Maloney, J. C.

(1994): Content: Covariation, control, and contingency. In: ' Synthese', vol. 100, pp.241-90.
@

Mameli, M.

(2002): Modules and mindreaders. In: 'Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 16, pp.377-93.
@

Mameli, M.

(2002): Mindreading, mindshaping, and evolution. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 16, pp.595-626.
@

Mameli, M.

(2004): The role of emotions in ecological and practical rationality. In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): 'Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality'. Oxford University Press.
@

Mandelbaum, M.

(1958): Professor Ryle and psychology. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 67, pp.522-30.
@

Mandelkar, S.

(1991): An argument against the externalist account of psychological content . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.375-82.
@

Manfredi, P.

(1993): Two routes to narrow content: both dead ends. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 6, pp.3-22.
@

Manfredi, P. A.

(1993): Tacit beliefs and other doxastic attitudes. In: ' 1993'.
@

Manfredi, P. A.; Summerfield, D. M.

(1992): Robustness without asymmetry: A flaw in Fodor's theory of content. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 66, pp.261-83.
@

Manier, E.

(1986): Problems in the development of cognitive neuroscience: Effective communication between scientific domains. In: 'Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 1986.
@

Manktelow, K.; Over, D.

(1987): Reasoning and rationality. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 2, pp.199-219.
@

Manning, R. C.

(1987): Why Sherlock Holmes can't be replaced by an expert system. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 51, pp.19-28.
@

Mannison, D. S.

(1975): Dreaming an impossible dream. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 4, pp.663-75.
@

Marcello, G.

(2000): Horgan and Tienson on ceteris paribus laws. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 67, pp.301-315.
@

Marconi, D.

(2005): Two-dimensional semantics and the articulation problem. In: 'Synthese', vol. 143, pp.321-49.
@

Marcus, E.

(2001): Mental causation: unnaturalized but not unnatural. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 63, pp.57-83.
@

Marcus, E.

(2005): Mental causation in a physical world. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 122, pp.27-50.
@

Marcus, G.

(2004): Birth of the Mind: How a Tiny Number of Genes Creates the Complexity of Human Thought. Basic Books.
@

Marcus, R. B.

(1995): The anti-naturalism of some language-centered accounts of beliefs . In: 'Dialectica', vol. 49, pp.113-30.
@

Margenau, H.

(1931): The uncertainty principle and free will. In: '1931 '.
@

Margolis, E.

(1995): The significance of the theory analogy in the psychological study of concepts. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 10, pp.45-71.
@

Margolis, E.

(1998): How to acquire a concept. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp.347-369.
@

Margolis, E.

(1999): What is conceptual glue?. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 9, pp.241-255.
@

Margolis, E.; Laurence, S.

(1998): Multiple meanings and stability of content. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.255-63.
@

Margolis, E.; Laurence, S.

(1999): Concepts: Core Readings. MIT Press.
@

Margolis, E.; Laurence, S.

(2002): Concepts. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Margolis, E.; Laurence, S.

(2002): Lewis's strawman. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 52, pp.55-65.
@

Margolis, J.

(1965): Brain processes and sensations. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 31, pp.133-38.
@

Margolis, J.

(1970): Indubitability, self-intimating states, and privileged access. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 67, pp.918-31.
@

Margolis, J.

(1978): Persons and Minds: The Prospects of Non-Reductive Materialism. D.
@

Margolis, J.

(1986): Emergence. In: 'Philosophical Forum ', vol. 17, pp.271-95.
@

Margolis, J.

(1988): Minds, selves, and persons. In: 'Topoi ', vol. 7, pp.31-45.
@

Margolis, J.

(1991): The autonomy of folk psychology. In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): ' The Future of Folk Psychology'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Mariano, L. B.

(1999): Content naturalized. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 96, pp.205-38.
@

Marinov, M.

(1993): On the spuriousness of the symbolic/subsymbolic distinction. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 3, pp.253-70.
@

Markic, O.

(2001): Is language of thought a conceptual necessity?. In: ' Acta Analytica', vol. 16, pp.53-60.
@

Markic, O.

(2002): Nonreductive materialism and the problem of causal exclusion. In: 'Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 63, pp.79-88.
@

Markman, A.; Stilwell, H. C.

(2004): Concepts a la modal: An extended review of Prinz's Furnishing the Mind. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 17, pp.391-401.
@

Marks, C.

(1980): Commissurotomy, Consciousness, and Unity of Mind. MIT Press.
@

Marks, J.

(1982): A theory of emotion. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 42, pp.227-42.
@

Marks, J.

(1986): The Ways of Desire: New Essays in Philosophical Psychology on the Concept of Wanting. Precedent.
@

Marks, J.

(1986): On the need for theory of desire. In: J. Marks (Ed.): ' The Ways of Desire'. Precedent.
@

Marqueze, J.

(2003): On orthodox and heterodox externalisms. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Marr, D.

(1977): Artificial intelligence: A personal view. In: ' Artificial Intelligence', vol. 9, pp.37-48.
@

Marr, D.

(1982): Vision. Freeman.
@

Marras, A.

(1985): The Churchlands on methodological solipsism and computational psychology . In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 52, pp.295-309.
@

Marras, A.

(1987): The weak and the strong representational theory of mind: Stich's interpretation of Fodor. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 26, pp.349-55.
@

Marras, A.

(1990): Reduction in psychology. In: 'Acta Analytica ', vol. 6, pp.65-78.
@

Marras, A.

(1993): Supervenience and reducibility: An odd couple. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 43, pp.215-222.
@

Marras, A.

(1993): Psychophysical supervenience and nonreductive materialism. In: 'Synthese', vol. 95, pp.275-304.
@

Marras, A.

(1994): Nonreductive materialism and mental causation. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 24, pp.465-93.
@

Marras, A.

(1994): Nonreductive materialism and mental causation. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 24, pp.465-93.
@

Marras, A.

(1997): The causal relevance of mental properties. In: ' Philosophia', vol. 25, pp.389-400.
@

Marras, A.

(1998): Kim's principle of explanatory exclusion. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 76, pp.439-451.
@

Marras, A.

(2001): On Putnam's critique of metaphysical realism: mind-body identity and supervenience. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 126, pp.407-426.
@

Marras, A.

(2002): Kim on reduction. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 57, pp.231-57.
@

Marras, A.

(2003): Methodological and ontological aspects of the mental causation problem . In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Martin, C. B.; Deutscher, M.

(1966): Remembering. In: 'Philosophical Revire ', vol. 75, pp.161-96.
@

Martin, C. B.; Heil, J,

(1998): Rules and powers. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 12, pp.283-312.
@

Martin, C. B.; Pfeifer, K.

(1986): Intentionality and the non-psychological. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 46, pp.531-54.
@

Martin, J.; Engleman, K.

(1990): The mind's I has two eyes. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 510.
@

Martin, M. G. F.

(1992): Perception, concepts, and memory. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 101, pp.745-63.
@

Martin, M. G. F.

(1998): An eye directed outward. In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Martin, M. G. F.

(2001): Out of the past: Episodic recall as retained acquaintance. In: C. Hoerl; T. McCormack (Ed.): 'Time and Memory'. Oxford University Press.
@

Martin, R.

(1987): Memory, connecting, and what matters in survival. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 65, pp.82-97.
@

Martin, R.

(1992): Self-interest and survival. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 29, pp.319-30.
@

Martin, R.

(1995): Fission rejuvenation. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 80, pp.17-40.
@

Martin, R.; Barresi, J.

(2004): Naturalizing the Soul: Self and Personal Identity in the Eighteenth Century. Routledge.
@

Martindale, R. L.; Seidel, R. J.

(1959): Reductionism: Its prodigal encores. In: 'Psychological Reports', vol. 5, pp.213-16.
@

Maslin, K. T.

(2001): An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Blackwell.
@

Matthen, M.

(1988): Biological functions and perceptual content. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 85, pp.5-27.
@

Matthen, M.

(2002): Human rationality and the unique origin constraint. In: A. Ariew (Ed.): 'Functions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Matthews, G. B.

(1977): Surviving as. In: 'Analysis', vol. 37, pp.53-58.
@

Matthews, G. B.

(1981): On being immoral in a dream. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 56, pp.47-64.
@

Matthews, R. J.

(1984): Troubles with representationalism. In: ' Social Research', vol. 51, pp.1065-97.
@

Matthews, R. J.

(1989): The alleged evidence for representationalism. In: S. Silvers (Ed.): 'Rerepresentation'. Kluwer.
@

Matthews, R. J.

(1991): Is there vindication through representationalism?. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Matthews, R. J.

(1994): The measure of mind. In: 'Mind ', vol. 103, pp.131-46.
@

Matthews, R. J.

(1994): Three-concept monte: Explanation, implementation, and systematicity . In: 'Synthese', vol. 101, pp.347-63.
@

Matthews, R. J.

(1997): Can connectionists explain systematicity?. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.154-77.
@

Matthews, R. J.

(2001): Cowie's anti-nativism. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 16, pp.215-230.
@

Matthews, S.

(1998): Personal identity, multiple personality disorder, and moral personhood . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 11, pp.67-88.
@

Matthews, S.

(2000): Survival and separation. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 98, pp.279-303.
@

Maudlin, T.

(1989): Computation and consciousness. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 86, pp.407-32.
@

Maudlin, T.

(1996): Between the motion and the act.. In: 'Psyche ', vol. 2, pp.40-51.
@

Maund, B.

(2003): Perception. Acumen.
@

Maund, J. B.

(1981): Colour: A case for conceptual fission. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 59, pp.308-22.
@

Maund, J. B.

(1991): The nature of color. In: ' History of Philosophy Quarterly', vol. 8, pp.253-63.
@

Maund, J. B.

(1995): Colours: Their Nature and Representation. Cambridge University Press.
@

Mausfeld, R.

(2004): Color Perception: Mind and the Physical World. Oxford University Press.
@

Mayr, U.

(2004): Conflict, consciousness, and control. In: ' Trends in Cognitive Science', vol. 8, pp.145-148.
@

Mays, W.

(1952): Can machines think?. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 27, pp.148-62.
@

Mays, W.

(1952): Can machines think?. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 27, pp.148-62.
@

McCall, C.

(1990): Concepts of Person: An Analysis of Concepts of Person, Self, and Human Being. Avebury.
@

McCall, S.

(1984): Freedom defined as the power to decide. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 21, pp.329-38.
@

McCall, S.

(1999): Can a Turing machine know that the Godel sentence is true?. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 96, pp.525-32.
@

McCall, S.

(2001): On "seeing" the truth of the Godel sentence. In: ' Facta Philosophica', vol. 3, pp.25-30.
@

McCann, H.

(1998): The Works of Agency: On Human Action, Will, and Freedom. Cornell University Press.
@

McCarthy, J.

(1979): Ascribing mental qualities to machines. In: M. Ringle (Ed.): 'Philosophical Perspectives in Artificial Intelligence'. Humanities Press.
@

McCarthy, J.

(1996): Making robots conscious of their mental states. In: S. Muggleton (Ed.): 'Machine Intelligence 15'. Oxford University Press.
@

McCarthy, J.; Hayes, P.

(1969): Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence. In: Meltzer; Michie (Ed.): ' Machine Intelligence 4'. Edinburgh University Press.
@

McCauley, R.

(1986): Intertheoretic relations and the future of psychology. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 53, pp.179-99.
@

McClamrock, R.

(1989): Holism without tears: Local and global effects in cognitive processing. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 56, pp.258-74.
@

McClamrock, R.

(1990): Marr's three levels: a re-evaluation. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.185-196.
@

McClamrock, R.

(1991): Methodological individualism considered as a constitutive principle of scientific inquiry. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.343-54.
@

McClamrock, R.

(1995): Existential Cognition: Computational Minds in the World. University of Chicago Press.
@

McClamrock, R.

(1995): Existential Cognition: Computational Minds in the World. University of Chicago Press.
@

McClelland, J. L.; Rumelhart, D. E.

(1985): Levels indeed! A response to Broadbent. In: 'Journal of Experimental Psychology: General', vol. 114, pp.193-7.
@

McCrone, J.

(1999): A bifold model of free will. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 5, pp.241-59.
@

McCullagh, C. B.

(1990): The rationality of emotions and of emotional behavior. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 68, pp.44-58.
@

McCullagh, M.

(2000): Functionalism and self-consciousness. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 15, pp.481-499.
@

McCullagh, M.

(2003): Do inferential roles compose?. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 57, pp.431-38.
@

McCulloch, G.

(1990): Dennett's little grains of salt. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 40, pp.1-12.
@

McCulloch, G.

(1992): The spirit of twin earth. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 52, pp.168-174.
@

McCulloch, G.

(1995): The Mind and its World. Routledge.
@

McCulloch, G.

(1998): Intentionality and interpretation. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

McCulloch, G.

(2002): Mental representation and mental presentation. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Logic, Thought, and Language'. Cambridge University Press.
@

McCullock, G.

(2002): The Life of the Mind. Routledge.
@

McCullough, D.

(1996): Can humans escape Godel?. In: 'Psyche ', vol. 2, pp.57-65.
@

McDermott, D.

(1978): Tarskian semantics, or no notation without denotation. In: 'Cognitive Science', vol. 2, pp.277-82.
@

McDermott, D.

(1981): Artificial intelligence meets natural stupidity. In: J. Haugeland (Ed.): 'Mind Design'. MIT Press.
@

McDermott, D.

(1987): We've been framed: Or, Why AI is innocent of the frame problem . In: Z. Pylyshyn (Ed.): 'The Robot's Dilemma'. Ablex.
@

McDermott, D.

(1987): A critique of pure reason. In: ' Computational Intelligence', vol. 3, pp.151-60.
@

McDermott, D.

(1996): Penrose is wrong. In: 'Psyche', vol. 2, pp.66-82.
@

McDermott, M.

(1986): Narrow content. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 64, pp.277-88.
@

McDermott, M.

(2001): Quine's holism and functionalist holism. In: 'Mind ', vol. 110, pp.977-1025.
@

McDonough, R.

(1991): Wittgenstein's refutation of meaning-scepticism. In: K. Puhl (Ed.): 'Meaning Scepticism'. De Gruyter.
@

McDonough, R.

(1991): A culturalist account of folk psychology. In: J. Greenwood (Ed.): 'The Future of Folk Psychology'. Cambridge University Press.
@

McDowell, J.

(1981): Non-cognitivism and rule-following. In: S. Holtzman; C. Leich (Ed.): 'Wittgenstein: To Follow A Rule'. Routledge.
@

McDowell, J.

(1984): Wittgenstein on following a rule. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 58.
@

McDowell, J.

(1985): Functionalism and anomalous monism. In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): 'Action and Events'. Blackwell.
@

McDowell, J.

(1991): Intentionality and interiority in wittgenstein: Comment on Crispin Wright. In: K. Puhl (Ed.): ' Meaning Scepticism'. De Gruyter.
@

McDowell, J.

(1992): Meaning and intentionality in Wittgenstein's later philosophy. In: 'Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 17.
@

McDowell, J.

(1995): Knowledge and the internal. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 55, pp.877-93.
@

McDowell, J.

(1998): Lecture III: Intentionality as a relation. In: ' Journal Of Philosophy', vol. 95, pp.471-491.
@

McFarland, D.; Miller, A.

(1998): Jackson on colour as a primary quality. In: 'Analysis', vol. 58, pp.76-85.
@

McFarland, D.; Miller, A.

(2000): Disjunctions, programming and the Australian view of colour. In: 'Analysis', vol. 60, pp.209-212.
@

McGeer, V.

(1996): Is "self-knowledge" an empirical problem? Renegotiating the space of philosophical explanation. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 93, pp.483-515.
@

McGilvray, J.

(1998): Meanings are syntactically individuated and found in the head. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.225-280.
@

McGilvray, J.

(1998): Meanings are syntactically individuated and found in the head. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.225-280.
@

McGilvray, J. A.

(1983): To color. In: 'Synthese', vol. 54, pp.37-70.
@

McGilvray, J. A.

(1994): Constant colors in the head. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 100, pp.197-239.
@

McGinn, C.

(1978): Mental states, natural kinds and psychophysical laws. In: 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 52, pp.195-220.
@

McGinn, C.

(1980): Philosophical materialism. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 44, pp.173-206.
@

McGinn, C.

(1980): Functionalism and phenomenalism: A critical note. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 58, pp.35-46.
@

McGinn, C.

(1982): The structure of content. In: A. Woodfield (Ed.): ' Thought and Object'. Oxford University Press.
@

McGinn, C.

(1982): The Character of Mind. Oxford University Press.
@

McGinn, C.

(1984): Wittgenstein on Meaning. Blackwell.
@

McGinn, C.

(1984): What is the problem of other minds?. In: ' Aristotelian Society Proceedings', vol. 58, pp.119-37.
@

McGinn, C.

(1987): Could a machine be conscious?. In: C. Blakemore; S. Greenfield (Ed.): 'Mindwaves'. Blackwell.
@

McGinn, C.

(1989): Mental Content. Blackwell.
@

McGinn, C.

(1991): Conceptual causation. In: 'Mind ', vol. 100, pp.525-46.
@

McGinn, C.

(1996): Another look at color. In: 'Journal of Philoophy ', vol. 93, pp.537-53.
@

McGinn, C.

(2005): Mindsight: Image, Dram, Meaning. Harvard University Press.
@

McGinn, M.

(1984): Kripke on Wittgenstein's Sceptical Problem. In: 'Ratio, ', vol. 26.
@

McGinn, M.

(1991): Westphal on the physical basis of color incompatibility. In: 'Analysis', vol. 4, pp.218-22.
@

McGinn, M.

(1991): On two recent accounts of color. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 41, pp.316-24.
@

McGinn, M.

(1998): The real problem of others: Cavell, Merleau-Ponty, and Wittgenstein on scepticism about other minds. In: 'European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 6, pp.45-58.
@

McGinn, M.

(2000): Real things and the mind-body problem. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 100, pp.303-17.
@

McGrath, M.

(1998): Proportionality and mental causation: A fit?. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 12, pp.167-176.
@

McInerney, P. K.

(1998): Persons and psychological systems. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 35, pp.179-193.
@

McInerney, P. K.

(2000): Conceptions of persons and persons through time. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 37, pp.121-134.
@

McIntyre, A.

(1994): Compatibilists could have done otherwise: Responsibility and negative agency. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 103.
@

McKay, T.; Johnson, D.

(1996): A reconsideration of an argument against compatibilism . In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 24, pp.113-22.
@

McKenna, M.

(1998): Does strong compatibilism survive Frankfurt-style counterexamples? . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 91, pp.259-64.
@

McKenna, M.; Widerker, D.

(2002): Freedom, Responsibility, and Action: Essays on the Importance of Alternative Possibilities. Ashgate Press.
@

McKinsey, M.

(1987): Apriorism in the philosophy of language. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 52, pp.1-32.
@

McKinsey, M.

(1991): The internal basis of meaning. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 72, pp.143-69.
@

McKinsey, M.

(1991): Anti-individualism and privileged access. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 51, pp.9-16.
@

McKinsey, M.

(1993): Curing folk psychology of arthritis. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 70, pp.323-36.
@

McKinsey, M.

(1994): Individuating beliefs. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 8, pp.303-30.
@

McKinsey, M.

(1994): Accepting the consequences of anti-individualism. In: ' Analysis', vol. 54, pp.124-8.
@

McKinsey, M.

(2002): Forms of externalism and privileged access. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 16, pp.199-224.
@

McKinsey, M.

(2002): On knowing our own minds. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 52, pp.107-16.
@

McKinsey, M.

(2003): Transmission of warrant and closure of apriority. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

McLaughlin, B.

(2000): Why intentional systems theory cannot reconcile physicalism with realism about belief and desire. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 14, pp.145-157.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1983): Event supervenience and supervenient causation. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 22, pp.71-91.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1985): Anomalous monism and the irreducibility of the mental. In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): 'Action and Events'. Blackwell.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1987): What is wrong with correlational psychosemantics. In: '1987'.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1989): Type epiphenomenalism, type dualism, and the causal priority of the physical. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 3, pp.109-135.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1992): The rise and fall of British emergentism. In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism'. De Gruyter.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1992): On Davidson's response to the charge of epiphenomenalism. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1992): Systematicity, conceptual truth, and evolution. In: '1992'.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1993): The connectionism/classicism battle to win souls. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 71.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1994): Varieties of supervenience. In (E. Savellos & O. In: '1994'.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1995): Varieties of supervenience. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(1997): Supervenience, vagueness, and determination. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 11, pp.209-30.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(2000): Self-knowledge, externalism, and skepticism. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 74, pp.93-118.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(2001): Introspecting thoughts. In: 'Facta Philosophica ', vol. 3, pp.77-84.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.

(2003): McKinsey's challenge, warrant transmission, and skepticism . In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.; LePore, E.

(1985): Actions and Events. Blackwell.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.; Tye, M.

(1998): Externalism, Twin Earth, and self-knowledge. In: C. Macdonald; P. Smith; C. Wright (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds: Essays in Self-Knowledge'. Oxford University Press.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.; Tye, M.

(1998): Is content-externalism compatible with privileged access? . In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 107, pp.349-380.
@

McLaughlin, B. P.; Warfield, F.

(1994): The allure of connectionism reexamined. In: 'Synthese', vol. 101, pp.365-400.
@

McLaughlin, B.; O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.

(1995): Dennett's logical behaviorism. In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 22, pp.189-258.
@

McLaughlin, B.; O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.

(1995): Dennett's logical behaviorism. In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 22, pp.189-258.
@

McManus, D.

(2000): Boghossian, Miller and Lewis on dispositional theories of meaning. Mind and Language 15:393-399. Miller, A. 1997. Boghossian on reductive dispositionalism about content: The case strengthened In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.1-10.
@

Measor, N.

(1980): On what matters in survival. In: 'Mind ', vol. 89, pp.406-11.
@

Meehl, P.

(1966): The compleat autocerebroscopist: A thought-experiment on Professor Feigl's mind-body identity thesis. In: P. Feyerabend; G. Maxwell (Ed.): ' Mind, Matter, and Method: Essays in Philosophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl'. University of Minnesota Press.
@

Meehl, P. E.; Sellars, W.

(1956): The concept of emergence. In: H. Feigl; M. Scriven (Ed.): 'Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science'. @

Mehler, J.; Fox, R.

(1985): Neonate Cognition: Beyond the Blooming Buzzing Confusion. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Meihers, A. W. M.

(1999): Belief, Cognition, and the Will. Tilburg University Press.
@

Meijers, A.

(2001): Explaining Beliefs. University of Chicago Press.
@

Meijers, A. W. M.

(1999): Believing and accepting as a group. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Belief, Cognition, and the Will'. Tilburg University Press.
@

Meiland, J. W.

(1966): Analogy, verification, and other minds. In: 'Mind ', vol. 75, pp.564-568.
@

Melchert, N.

(1986): What's wrong with anomalous monism. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 80, pp.265-74.
@

Melden, A. I.

(1961): Free Action. Routledge.
@

Mele, A.

(1995): Autonomous Agents: From Self-Control to Autonomy. Oxford University Press.
@

Mele, A.

(1996): Soft libertarianism and Frankfurt-style scenarios. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 24, pp.123-41.
@

Mele, A.

(1999): Kane, luck, and the significance of free will. In: ' Philosophical Explorations', vol. 2, pp.96-104.
@

Mele, A.

(2001): Self-Deception Unmasked. Princeton University Press.
@

Mele, A.

(2002): Autonomy, self-control and weakness of will. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Mele, A. R.

(1987): Irrationality: An Essay on Akrasia, Self-Deception, and Self-Control . Oxford University Press.
@

Mele, A. R.

(1990): Irresistible desires. In: 'Nous ', vol. 24, pp.455-72.
@

Mele, A.; Robb, D.

(1998): Rescuing Frankfurt-style cases. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 107, pp.97-112.
@

Mellor, D. H.

(1984): What is computational psychology? II. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 58, pp.37-53.
@

Mellor, D. H.

(1989): How much of the mind is a computer. In: P. Slezak (Ed.): ' Computers, Brains and Minds'. Kluwer.
@

Mellor, W. W.

(1956): Three problems about other minds. In: 'Mind ', vol. 65, pp.200-217.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1991): Physicalism: From supervenience to elimination. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 51, pp.573-87.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1994): Inference to the best explanation and other minds. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 4, pp.482-91.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1995): Two cheers for reductionism, or, the dim prospects for nonreductive materialism. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 62, pp.370-88.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1996): Testament of a recovering eliminativist. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 63.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1996): The prospects for Dretske's account of the explanatory role of belief . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 11, pp.203-15.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1996): Formulating physicalism: Two suggestions. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 105, pp.381-407.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1996): Searle's abstract argument against strong AI. In: ' Synthese', vol. 108, pp.391-419.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1997): On the metaphysical utility of claims of global supervenience. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 87, pp.277-308.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1997): On the metaphysical utility of claims of global supervenience. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 87, pp.277-308.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1997): How to keep the 'physical' in physicalism. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 94, pp.622-637.
@

Melnyk, A.

(1998): The prospects for Kirk's nonreductive physicalism. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 76, pp.323-32.
@

Melnyk, A.

(2002): Physicalism. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Melnyk, A.

(2003): Some evidence for physicalism. In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Mendola, J.

(2003): A dilemma for asymmetric dependence. In: 'Nous ', vol. 37, pp.232-257.
@

Menzies, P.

(2003): The causal efficacy of mental states. In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Merricks, T.

(1997): Fission and personal identity over time. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 88, pp.163-186.
@

Merricks, T.

(1997): Fission and personal identity over time. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 88, pp.163-186.
@

Merricks, T.

(1998): Against the doctrine of microphysical supervenience. In: 'Mind', vol. 107.
@

Merricks, T.

(1998): Against the doctrine of microphysical supervenience. In: 'Mind', vol. 107, pp.59-71.
@

Merricks, T.

(2000): Perdurance and psychological continuity. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 61, pp.195-199.
@

Merricks, T.

(2001): Objects and Persons. Oxford University Press.
@

Meyering, T.

(2001): The causal powers of belief: A critique from practical realism. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): 'Explaining Beliefs'. CSLI.
@

Meyering, T. C.

(1994): Fodor's modularity: A new name for an old dilemma. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.39-62.
@

Michie, D.

(1993): Turing's test and conscious thought. In: ' Artificial Intelligence', vol. 60, pp.1-22.
@

Millar, A.

(2001): Rationality and higher-order intentionality. In: ' Philosophy Supplement', vol. 49, pp.179-198.
@

Millar, A.

(2002): The normativity of meaning. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Logic, Thought, and Language'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Millar, A.

(2004): Understanding People: Normativity and Rationalizing Explanation. Oxford University Press.
@

Millar, P.

(1973): On the point of the Imitation Game. In: 'Mind ', vol. 82, pp.595-97.
@

Miller, A.

(1993): Some anomalies in Kim's account of Davidson. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 31, pp.335-44.
@

Miller, A.

(2001): The missing-explanation argument revisited. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 61, pp.76-86.
@

Miller, A.

(2003): Does "belief holism" show that reductive dispositionalism about content could not be true?. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 77, pp.73-90.
@

Miller, A.; Wright, C.

(2002): Rule-Following and Meaning. Acumen.
@

Miller, D. S.

(1911): Is consciousness "a type of behaviour"?. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 8, pp.322-27.
@

Miller, D. S.

(1951): "Descartes myth" and "Professor Ryle's fallacy". In: ' 1951'.
@

Miller, R. B.

(1990): Supervenience is a two-way street. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 87, pp.695-701.
@

Miller, R. B.

(1997): One bad and one not very good argument against holism. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 75, pp.234-40.
@

Miller, R. W.

(1997): Externalist self-knowledge and the scope of the a priori. In: 'Analysis', vol. 57, pp.67-74.
@

Millikan, D.

(1999): Historical kinds and the "special sciences". In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 95, pp.45-65.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1979): An evolutionist approach to language. In: ' Philosophy Research Archives', vol. 5.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1984): Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories. MIT Press.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1986): Thoughts without laws: Cognitive science with content. In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 95, pp.47-80.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1986): Thoughts without laws: Cognitive science with content. In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 95, pp.47-80.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1989): Biosemantics. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 86, pp.281-97.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1989): In defense of proper functions. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 56, pp.288-302.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1990): Compare and contrast Dretske, Fodor, and Millikan on teleosemantics . In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 18, pp.151-61.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1990): Truth, rules, hoverflies, and the Kripke-Wittgenstein paradox . In: 'Philosophical Review,', vol. 99, pp.323-53.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1991): Speaking up for Darwin. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): ' Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1993): On mentalese orthography. In: B. Dahlbom (Ed.): ' Dennett and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1993): White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1993): Explanation in biopsychology. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1994): On unclear and indistinct ideas. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 8, pp.75-100.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1995): Pushmi-pullyu representations. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.185-200.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1996): On swampkinds. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp.103-17.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1997): Troubles with Wagner's reading of Millikan. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 86, pp.93-96.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(1997): A common structure for concepts of individuals, stuffs, and kinds: More mama, more milk, and more mouse. In: '1997'.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(2001): What has natural information to do with intentional representation? . In: D. Walsh (Ed.): 'Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(2002): Biofunctions: Two paradigms. In: A. Ariew (Ed.): ' Functions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Millikan, R. G.

(2004): Varieties of Meaning. MIT Press.
@

Mills E.

(1993): Dividing without reducing: Bodily fission and personal identity. In: 'Mind', vol. 102, pp.37-51.
@

Mills, E.

(1996): Interactionism and overdetermination. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 33, pp.105-115.
@

Mills, E.

(1997): Interactionism and physicality. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 10, pp.169-83.
@

Mills, S.

(1989): Connectionism, the classical theory of cognition, and the hundred step constraint. In: 'Acta Analytica ', vol. 4, pp.5-38.
@

Minar, E.

(1991): Wittgenstein and the "contingency" of community. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly,', vol. 72.
@

Miri, M.

(1973): Memory and personal identity. In: 'Mind ', vol. 82, pp.1-21.
@

Miscevic, N.

(1996): Computation, content, and cause. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 82, pp.241-63.
@

Miscevic, N.

(1996): Computationalism and the Kripke-Wittgenstein paradox. In: 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 96, pp.215-29.
@

Miscevic, N.

(2001): Apriority and conceptual kinematics. In: ' Croatian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 1, pp.21-48.
@

Moller, D.

(2002): Parfit on pains, pleasures, and the time of their occurrence. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 31, pp.67-82.
@

Momeyer, R.

(1975): Is pleasure a sensation?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 36, pp.113-21.
@

Montero, B.

(1999): The body problem. In: 'Nous', vol. 33, pp.183-200.
@

Montero, B.

(2001): Post-physicalism. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies ', vol. 8, pp.61-80.
@

Montero, B.

(2003): Varieties of causal closure. In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Montgomery, R.

(1990): The reductionist ideal in cognitive psychology. In: ' Synthese', vol. 85, pp.279-314.
@

Montgomery, R.

(1995): Non-Cartesian explanations meet the problem of mental causation . In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 33, pp.221-41.
@

Montgomery, R.

(1995): Explanation and evaluation in cognitive science. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 62, pp.261-82.
@

Montgomery, R.

(1996): The indeterminacy of color vision. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 106, pp.167-203.
@

Montgomery, R.

(1998): Grades of explanation in cognitive science. In: ' Synthese', vol. 114, pp.463-495.
@

Moody, T. C.

(1993): Philosophy and Artificial Intelligence. Prentice-Hall.
@

Moor, J.

(1982): Split brains and atomic persons. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 49, pp.91-106.
@

Moor, J. H.

(1976): An analysis of Turing's test. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 30, pp.249-257.
@

Moor, J. H.

(1978): Explaining computer behavior. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 34, pp.325-7.
@

Moor, J. H.

(1988): The pseudorealization fallacy and the Chinese Room argument. In: J. Fetzer (Ed.): 'Aspects of AI'. D.
@

Moor, J. H.

(2001): The status and future of the Turing test. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 11, pp.77-93.
@

Moore, G. E.

(1912): Free will. In: 'Ethics'.
@

Moran, R.

(1988): Making up your mind: Self-interpretation and self-constitution. In: 'Ratio', vol. 1, pp.135-51.
@

Moran, R.

(1994): Interpretation theory and the first-person. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 44, pp.154-73.
@

Moran, R.

(1997): Self-knowledge: Discovery, resolution, and undoing. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.141-61.
@

Moran, R.

(2001): Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-Knowledge. Princeton University Press.
@

Moran, R.

(2003): Responses to O'Brien and Shoemaker. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 11, pp.402-19.
@

Morden, M.

(1990): Free will, self-causation, and strange loops. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 68, pp.59-73.
@

Moreland, J. P.

(1999): Should a naturalist be a supervenient physicalist?. In: 'Metaphilosophy', vol. 29, pp.35-57.
@

Moreland, J. P.

(2002): Timothy O'Connor and the harmony thesis: A critique. In: 'Metaphysica', vol. 3, no.2, pp.5-40.
@

Morgan, C. L.

(1923): Emergent Evolution. Williams and Norgate.
@

Morgan, V.

(2001): The metaphysics of naturalism. In: ' American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 75, pp.409-431.
@

Morgenbesser, S.; Walsh, J. J.

(1962): Freedom and Responsibility. Prentice-Hall.
@

Morick, H.

(1967): Wittgenstein and the Problem of Other Minds. Humanities Press.
@

Morin, A.

(2001): The split brain debate revisited: on the importance of language and self recognition for right hemispheric consciousness . In: 'Journal Of Mind and Behavior', vol. 22, pp.107-118.
@

Morreal, J.

(1983): Humor and emotion. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 20, pp.297-304.
@

Morris, C. R.

(1926): The notion of emergence. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 6, pp.49-55.
@

Morris, K. J.

(1996): Pain, injury, and first/third-person asymmetry. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.125-56.
@

Morris, M.

(1986): Causes of behavior. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 36, pp.123-44.
@

Morris, M.

(1991): Why there are no mental representations. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.1-30.
@

Morris, P. E.; Hampson, P. J.

(1983): Imagery and Consciousness. Academic Press.
@

Morris, W. E.

(1990): The regularity theory of information. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 82, pp.375-398.
@

Mortensen, C.

(1989): Mental images: Should cognitive science learn from neurophysiology? . In: P. Slezak (Ed.): 'Computers, Brains and Minds'. Kluwer.
@

Morton, A.

(1980): Frames of Mind. Oxford University Press.
@

Morton, A.

(1991): The inevitability of folk psychology. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): ' Mind and Common Sense'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Morton, A.

(1996): Folk psychology is not a predictive device. In: 'Mind ', vol. 105, pp.119-37.
@

Morton, A.

(2003): Saving belief from (internalist) epistemology. In: ' Facta Philosophica', vol. 5, pp.277-95.
@

Morton, P.

(1993): Supervenience and computational explanation in vision theory. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 60, pp.86-99.
@

Moser, P,; Trout, J. D.

(1996): Physicalism, supervenience, and dependence. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Moser, P.

(1991): Malcolm on Wittgenstein on rules. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp.101-105.
@

Moser, P.

(1992): Beyond the private language argument. In: 'Metaphilosophy ', vol. 23, pp.77-89.
@

Moser, P.

(1994): Naturalism and psychological explanation. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.63-84.
@

Moser, P. K.

(1990): Physicalism and intentional attitudes. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 18, pp.33-41.
@

Moser, P. K.

(1992): Physicalism and global supervenience. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 30, pp.71-82.
@

Moser, P. K.

(1996): Physicalism and mental causes: Contra Papineau. In: ' Analysis', vol. 56, pp.263-67.
@

Mosterin, J.

(2002): Acceptance without belief. In: 'Manuscrito ', vol. 25, pp.313-35.
@

Mott, P.

(1992): Fodor and ceteris paribus laws. In: 'Mind ', vol. 101, pp.335-46.
@

Mounce, H. O.

(1986): Following a rule. In: 'Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 9, pp.187-198.
@

Moya, C.

(2003): Externalism, inclusion, and knowledge of content. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Mucciolo, L.

(1974): The identity thesis and neuropsychology. In: 'Nous ', vol. 8, pp.327-42.
@

Mucciolo, L.

(1974): The identity theory and criteria for the mental. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 35, pp.167-80.
@

Mucciolo, L.

(1974): The identity thesis and neuropsychology. In: 'Nous ', vol. 8, pp.327-42.
@

Mumford, S.

(1999): Intentionality and the physical: A new theory of disposition ascription . In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.215-25.
@

Mundale, J.

(2001): Neuroanatomical foundations of cognition: Connecting the neuronal level with the study of higher brain areas. In: W. Bechtel; P. Mandik; J. Mundale; and R. Stufflebeam (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader'. Blackwell.
@

Mundale, J.

(2002): Concepts of localization: Balkanization in the brain. In: 'Brain and Mind', vol. 3, pp.313-30.
@

Mundale, J.; Bechtel, W.

(1996): Integrating neuroscience, psychology, and evolutionary biology through a teleological conception of function. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 6, pp.481-505.
@

Munsat, S.

(1969): Could sensations be processes?. In: 'Mind ', vol. 78, pp.247-51.
@

Munsat, S.

(1979): Memory and causality. In: D. Gustafson (Ed.): ' Body, Mind, and Method'. Reidel.
@

Murphy, D.

(2001): Folk psychology meets the frame problem. In: ' Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics', vol. 32.
@

Murphy, D.

(2005): Psychiatry in the Scientific Image. MIT Press.
@

Myin, E.

(2001): Color and the duplication assumption. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 129, pp.61-77.

N


@

Nagasawa, Y.

(2002): Externalism and the memory argument. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 56, pp.335-46.
@

Nagel, E.

(1949): Are naturalists materialists?. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 42, pp.515-53.
@

Nagel, T.

(1965): Physicalism. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 74, pp.339-56.
@

Nagel, T.

(1971): Brain bisection and the unity of consciousness. In: ' Synthese', vol. 22, pp.396-413.
@

Nahmias, E.; Morris, S.; Nadelhoffer, T.

(2004): The phenomenology of free will. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 11.
@

Nakamura, Y.; Chapman, C.

(2002): Constructing pain: How pain hurts. In: K. Yasue; M. Jibu; T. Senta (Ed.): 'No Matter, Never Mind'. John Benjamins.
@

Nakashima, H.

(1999): AI as complex information processing. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 9, pp.57-80.
@

Nakhnikian, G.

(1968): Incorrigibility. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 18, pp.207-15.
@

Nannini, S.

(2004): Mental causation and intentionality in a mind naturalising theory . In: A. Peruzzi (Ed.): 'Mind and Causality'. John Benjamins.
@

Narayanan, A.

(1996): The intentional stance and the imitation game. In: P. Millican; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Machines and Thought'. Oxford University Press.
@

Narveson, A. H.

(1966): Evidential necessity and other minds. In: 'Mind ', vol. 75.
@

Narveson, J.

(1977): Compatibilism defended. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 32, pp.83-7.
@

Nash, R. A.

(1989): Cognitive theories of emotion. In: 'Nous ', vol. 23, pp.481-504.
@

Nasrin, M.

(2000): Multiple realizability: Also a difficulty for functionalism. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 7, pp.25-34.
@

Nasrin, M.

(2004): Anomalous monism in Carnap's Aufbau. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 60, pp.283-293.
@

Nathan, N.

(1992): Will and World. Oxford University Press.
@

Naylor, A.

(1985): In defense of a nontraditional theory of memory. In: ' Monist', vol. 62, pp.136-50.
@

Naylor, M. B.

(1984): Frankfurt on the principle of alternative possibilities. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 46, pp.249-58.
@

Neander, K.

(1995): Misrepresenting and malfunctioning. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 79, pp.109-41.
@

Neander, K.

(1995): Dretske's innate modesty. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 74, pp.258-74.
@

Neander, K.

(1996): Swampman meets swampcow. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp.118-29.
@

Neely, W.

(1974): Freedom and desire. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 83, pp.32-54.
@

Negley, G.

(1951): Cybernetics and theories of mind. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 48, pp.574-82.
@

Neisser, U.

(1981): Concepts and Conceptual Development. Cambridge University Press.
@

Neisser, U.

(1991): Five kinds of self-knowledge. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 1, pp.35-59.
@

Nelkin, D.

(2001): The consequence argument and the "mind" argument. In: ' Analysis', vol. 61, pp.107-115.
@

Nelkin, N.

(1986): Pains and pain sensations. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 83, pp.129-48.
@

Nelkin, N.

(1993): Patterns. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.56-87.
@

Nelkin, N.

(1994): Reconsidering pain. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 7, pp.325-43.
@

Nelson, A.

(1985): Physical properties. In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 66, pp.268-82.
@

Nelson, E.

(2002): Mathematics and the mind. In: K. Yasue; M. Jibu; T. Senta (Ed.): 'No Matter, Never Mind'. John Benjamins.
@

Nelson, J.

(1983): Do animals propositionally know? Do they propositionally believe? . In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 20, pp.149-60.
@

Nelson, R.

(1969): Behaviorism is false. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp.417-52.
@

Nelson, R.

(1974): Mechanism, functionalism, and the identity theory. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 73, pp.365-86.
@

Nelson, R.

(1975): Behaviorism, finite automata, and stimulus-response theory. In: 'Theory and Decision', vol. 6, pp.249-67.
@

Nelson, R.

(1987): Machine models for cognitive science. In: '1987'.
@

Nelson, R.

(1989): Philosophical issues in Edelman's neural darwinism. In: ' Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 1, pp.195-208.
@

Nerlich, G. C.

(1958): Sameness, difference, and continuity. In: '1958'.
@

Neu, J.

(1971): Emotion, Thought, and Therapy. Cambridge University Press.
@

Neu, J.

(2000): A Tear is an Intellectual Thing: The Meanings of Emotion. Oxford University Press.
@

Neu, J.

(2004): Emotions and freedom. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Newell, A.

(1980): Physical symbol systems. In: 'Cognitive Science ', vol. 4, pp.135-83.
@

Newell, A.

(1982): The knowledge level. In: 'Artificial Intelligence ', vol. 18, pp.81-132.
@

Newell, A.

(1986): The symbol level and the knowledge level. In: Z. Pylyshyn; W. Demopolous (Ed.): 'Meaning and Cognitive Structure'. Ablex.
@

Newell, A.; Simon, H.A.

(1981): Computer science as empirical inquiry: Symbols and search . In: 'Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery', vol. 19, pp.113-26.
@

Newen, A.

(2001): Contextual realism: The context-dependency and the relational character of beliefs. In: A. Meijers (Ed.): ' Explaining Beliefs'. CSLI.
@

Newman, A.

(2004): The good, the bad, and the irrational: Three views of mental content . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 17, pp.95-106.
@

Newman, A. E.

(2005): Two grades of internalism (pass and fail). In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 122.
@

Newman, D.

(1996): Emergence and strange attractors. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 63, pp.245-61.
@

Newman, D. V.

(2001): Chaos, emergence, and the mind-body problem. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 79, pp.180-96.
@

Newton, N.

(1989): Machine understanding and the Chinese Room. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 2, pp.207-15.
@

Newton, N.

(1989): On viewing pain as a secondary quality. In: 'Nous ', vol. 23, pp.569-98.
@

Newton, N.

(1992): Dennett on intrinsic intentionality. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 52, pp.18-23.
@

Newton, N.

(1996): Foundations of Understanding. John Benjamins.
@

Newton, N.

(2001): Emergence and the uniqueness of consciousness. In: ' Journal Of Consciousness Studies', vol. 8, pp.47-59.
@

Nichols, S.

(2000): The mind's "I" and the theory of mind's "I": Introspection and two concepts of self. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 28, pp.171-99.
@

Nichols, S.

(2002): Imagination and the puzzles of iteration. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 63, pp.182-87.
@

Nichols, S.

(2004): The folk psychology of free will: Fits and starts. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.473-502.
@

Nichols, S.

(2004): Imagining and believing: The promise of a single code. In: 'Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism', vol. 62, pp.129-39.
@

Nichols, S.; Stich, S.

(1998): Rethinking co-cognition: A reply to Heal. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.499-512.
@

Nichols, S.; Stich, S.

(2003): Mindreading. An Integrated Account of Pretence, Self-Awareness, and Understanding Other Minds. Oxford University Press.
@

Nichols, S.; Stich, S.; Leslie, A.

(1995): Choice effects and the ineffectiveness of simulation. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 10, pp.437-45.
@

Nichols, S.; Stich, S.; Leslie, A.; Klein, D.

(1996): Varieties of off-line simulation . In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Nida-Rumelin, M.

(1997): The character of color predicates: A phenomenalist view. In: M. Anduschus; A. Newen; W. Kunne (Ed.): 'Direct Reference, Indexicality, and Propositional Attitudes'. CSLI Press.
@

Niklasson, L. F.; van Gelder, T.

(1994): On being systematically connectionist. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.288-302.
@

Nilsson, N.

(1991): Logic and artificial intelligence. In: ' Artificial Intelligence', vol. 47, pp.31-56.
@

Nimtz, C.

(2004): Two-dimensionalism and natural kind terms. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 138, pp.125-48.
@

Nimtz, C.; Schutte, M.

(2003): On physicalism, physical properties, and panpsychism. In: 'Dialectica', vol. 57, pp.413-22.
@

Nisbett, R.; Ross, L.

(1980): Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment. Prentice-Hall.
@

Noe, A.; Thompson, E.

(2002): Vision and Mind: Selected Readings in the Philosophy of Perception. MIT Press.
@

Noonan, H.

(1987): Supervenience. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 37, pp.78-85.
@

Noonan, H.

(1989): Personal Identity. Routledge.
@

Noonan, H.

(1993): Chisholm, persons, and identity. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 69, pp.35-58.
@

Noonan, H.

(1999): Microphysical supervenience and consciousness. In: 'Mind ', vol. 108, pp.755-9.
@

Noonan, H.

(2003): Personal Identity. Routledge.
@

Noonan, H. W.

(1984): Methodological solipsism: A reply to Morris. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 48, pp.285-290.
@

Noonan, H. W.

(1986): Russellian thoughts and methodological solipsism. In: J. Butterfield (Ed.): 'Language, Mind, and Logic'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Noonan, H. W.

(1990): Object-dependent thoughts and psychological redundancy. In: 'Analysis', vol. 51, pp.1-9.
@

Noonan, H. W.

(1993): Object-dependent thoughts: A case of superficial necessity but deep contingency?. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Noonan, P.

(2004): Against absence-dependent thoughts. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 64, pp.92-93.
@

Noordhof, P.

(1996): Accidental associations, local potency, and a dilemma for Dretske . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 11, pp.216-22.
@

Noordhof, P.

(1997): Making the change: The functionalist's way. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 48, pp.233-50.
@

Noordhof, P.

(1998): Do tropes resolve the problem of mental causation?. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 48, pp.221-26.
@

Noordhof, P.

(1999): Micro-based properties and the supervenience argument: A response to Kim. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 99, pp.115-18.
@

Noordhof, P.

(2002): Personal dualism and the argument from differential vagueness. In: 'Philosophical Papers', vol. 31, pp.63-86.
@

Noordhof, P.

(2002): Imagining objects and imagining experiences. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 17, pp.426-455.
@

Noordhof, P.

(2002): Imagining objects and imagining experiences. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 17, pp.426-455.
@

Noordhof, P.

(2003): Self-deception, interpretation and consciousness. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 67, pp.75-100.
@

Noordhof, P.

(2003): Not old... but not that new either: Explicability, emergence, and the characterisation of materialism. In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Noordhof, P.

(2004): Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument?. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 64, pp.48-56.
@

Noordhof, P.

(2005): The transmogrification of a posteriori knowledge: Reply to Brueckner . In: 'Analysis', vol. 65.
@

Nordby, H.

(2005): Davidson on social externalism. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 86.
@

Noren, S. J.

(1970): Identity, materialism, and the problem of the danglers. In: 'Metaphilosophy', vol. 4, pp.318-44.
@

Noren, S. J.

(1970): Smart's materialism: The identity thesis and translation. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 48, pp.54-66.
@

Noren, S. J.

(1979): Anomalous monism, events, and `the mental'. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 40, pp.64-74.
@

Normore, C.

(2003): Burge, Descartes, and us. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): ' Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Northoff, G.

(2000): Are "q-memories" empirically realistic?: A neurophilosophical approach . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.191-211.
@

Northoff, G.

(2001): "Brain-paradox" and "embeddment": Do we need a "philosophy of the brain"?. In: 'Brain and Mind ', vol. 195.
@

Northoff, G.

(2004): Philosophy of the Brain: The Brain Problem. John Benjamins.
@

Norton, R.

(1964): On the identity of identity theories. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 25, pp.14-16.
@

Nowell-Smith, P.

(1948): Free will and moral responsibility. In: 'Mind ', vol. 57, pp.45-61.
@

Nozick, R.

(1981): The identity of the self. In: 'Philosophical Explanations '.
@

Nozick, R.

(1993): The Nature of Rationality. Princeton University Press.
@

Nuccetelli, S.

(1999): What anti-individualist cannot know a priori. In: ' Analysis', vol. 59, pp.48-51.
@

Nuccetelli, S.

(2001): Is self-knowledge an entitlement? And why should we care?. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 39, pp.143-155.
@

Nuccetelli, S.

(2003): Knowing that one knows what one is talking about. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Nuccetelli, S.

(2003): New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge. MIT Press.
@

Nussbaum, C.

(2003): Another look at functionalism and the emotions. In: ' Brain and Mind', vol. 4, pp.353-383.
@

Nussbaum, M.

(1990): Love's Knowledge. Oxford University Press.
@

Nussbaum, M.

(2001): Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge University Press.
@

Nussbaum, M.

(2004): Emotions as judgments of value and importance. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.

O


@

O'Brien, G.

(1987): Eliminative materialism and our psychological self-knowledge. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 52, pp.49-70.
@

O'Brien, G.

(1991): Is connectionism commonsense?. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.165-78.
@

O'Brien, G.; Opie, J.

(2004): Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation . In: H. Clapin (Ed.): 'Representation in Mind'. Elsevier.
@

O'Brien, L.

(2003): Moran on agency and self-knowledge. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 11, pp.391-401.
@

O'Brien, L.

(2005): Imagination and the motivational role of belief. In: ' Analysis', vol. 65, pp.55-62.
@

O'Connor, D. J.

(1971): Free Will. Anchor Books.
@

O'Connor, T.

(1993): Indeterminism and free agency: Three recent views. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 53, pp.499-26.
@

O'Connor, T.

(1993): On the transfer of necessity. In: 'Nous ', vol. 27, pp.204-18.
@

O'Connor, T.

(1994): Emergent properties. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 31, pp.91-104.
@

O'Connor, T.

(1995): Agents, Causes, and Events: Essays on Indeterminism and Free Will . Oxford University Press.
@

O'Connor, T.

(1995): Agent causation. In: ' Agents, Causes, and Events: Essays on Indeterminism and Free Will'.
@

O'Connor, T.

(1996): Why agent causation?. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 24, pp.143-58.
@

O'Connor, T.

(2000): Persons and Causes: The Metaphysics of Free Will. Oxford University Press.
@

O'Connor, T.

(2002): Libertarian views: Dualist and agent-causal theories. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

O'Connor, T.; Robb, D.

(2003): Philosophy of Mind: Contemporary Readings. Routledge.
@

O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.

(1994): On the threat of eliminativism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 74, pp.325-46.
@

O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.; McDonough, J. K.

(1998): Numbers, minds, and bodies: A fresh look at mind-body dualism. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 12, pp.349-371.
@

O'Leary-Hawthorne, J.; Pettit, P.

(1996): Strategies for free will compatibilists. In: 'Analysis', vol. 56, pp.191-201.
@

O'Nuillain, S.

(1995): The Search for Mind: A New Foundation for Cognitive Science. Ablex.
@

O'Nuillain, S.; McKevitt, P.; MacAogain, E.

(1997): Two Sciences of Mind. John Benjamins.
@

O'Regan, K.

(1992): Solving the "real" mysteries of visual perception: The world as an outside memory. In: ' Canadian Journal of Psychology', vol. 46, pp.461-88.
@

O'Shaughnessy, B.

(1980): The Will: A Dual Aspect Theory. Cambridge University Press.
@

Oaklander, L. N.

(1987): Parfit, circularity, and the unity of consciousness. In: 'Mind', vol. 96, pp.525-29.
@

Oaksford, M.; Chater, N.; Stenning, K.

(1990): Connectionism, classical cognitive science and experimental psychology. In: '1990'.
@

Obermeier, K. K.

(1983): Wittgenstein on language and artificial intelligence: The Chinese-room thought-experiment revisited. In: 'Synthese', vol. 56, pp.339-50.
@

Oddie, G.

(1991): Supervenience and higher-order universals. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 69, pp.20-47.
@

Oddie, G.; Tichy, P.

(1990): Resplicing properties in the supervenience base. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 58, pp.259-69.
@

Oderberg, D.

(1989): Johnston on human beings. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 86, pp.137-41.
@

Oderberg, D. S.

(1987): Kripke and "quus". Theoria 53:115-20. pp. In: '1 ', vol. 15.
@

Okasha, S.

(2003): Fodor on cognition, modularity, and adaptationism. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 70, pp.68-88.
@

Olivier, A.

(2002): When pain becomes unreal. In: 'Philosophy Today ', vol. 2, pp.113-131.
@

Olivier, A.

(2003): When pains are mental objects. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 115, pp.33-53.
@

Olshewsky, T. M.

(1975): Dispositions and reductionism in psychology. In: ' Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior', vol. 5, pp.129-44.
@

Olson E.

(1994): Is Psychology relevant to personal identity?. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 72, pp.173-186.
@

Olson, E.

(1998): Human atoms. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 76, pp.396-406.
@

Olson, E.

(2001): Personal identity and the radiation argument. In: ' Analysis', vol. 61, pp.38-44.
@

Olson, E.

(2002): Personal identity. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Olson, E.

(2004): Animalism and the corpse problem. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 82, pp.265-74.
@

Olson, E. T.

(1997): The Human Animal: Personal Identity without Psychology. Oxford University Press.
@

Olsson, E.

(1997): Coherence and the modularity of mind. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 75, pp.404-11.
@

Oltmanns, T. F.; Maher, B. A.

(1988): Delusional Beliefs. John Wiley.
@

Oosthuizen, D. C. S.

(1970): Phenomenological psychology. In: 'Mind ', vol. 79, pp.487-501.
@

Oppy, G.; Dowe, D.

(2003): The Turing test. In: '2003'.
@

Orden, van, G. C.

(1997): Functional neuroimages fail to discover pieces of mind in the parts of the brain. In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement', vol. 64, pp.85-94.
@

Osherson, D. N.; Smith, E. E.

(1981): On the adequacy of prototype theory as a theory of concepts. In: 'Cognition', vol. 9, pp.35-58.
@

Ostein, P. A.

(1974): God, other minds, and the inference to the best explanation. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 4, pp.149-62.
@

Over, D.

(2002): The rationality of evolutionary psychology. In: J. Bermudez and A. Millar (Ed.): 'Reason and Nature'. Clarendon.
@

Owens, D.

(1996): A Lockean theory of memory experience. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.319-32.
@

Owens, D.

(1999): The authority of memory. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 7, pp.312-29.
@

Owens, D.

(2003): Externalis, Davidson, and knowledge of comparative content. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Owens, D.

(2003): Knowing your own mind. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 42, pp.791-798.
@

Owens, D. J.

(2003): Does belief have an aim?. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 115, pp.283-305.
@

Owens, J.

(1982): The failure of Lewis's functionalism. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 36, pp.159-73.
@

Owens, J.

(1983): Functionalism and the propositional attitudes. In: 'Nous ', vol. 17, pp.529-49.
@

Owens, J.

(1987): In defense of a different Doppelganger. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 96, pp.521-54.
@

Owens, J.

(1992): Psychophysical supervenience: Its epistemological foundation. In: 'Synthese', vol. 90, pp.89-117.
@

Owens, J.

(1993): Content, causation, and psychophysical supervenience. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 60, pp.242-61.
@

Owens, J.

(1998): Psychological explanation and causal deviancy. In: ' Synthese', vol. 115, pp.143-169.
@

Owens, J.

(2003): Anti-individualism, indexicality, and character. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.

P


@

Pacherie, E.

(2000): The content of intentions. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 15, pp.400-432.
@

Pacherie, E.

(2001): Conscious experience and concept-forming abilities. In: 'Acta Analytica', vol. 16, pp.45-52.
@

Pacherie, E.

(2002): Reply to 'Joint attention and simulaton'. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Pacherie, E.

(2002): The role of emotions in the explanation of action. In: 'European Review of Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.53-92.
@

Pagin, P.

(1997): Is compositionality compatible with holism?. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.11-33.
@

Pap, A.

(1951): The concept of absolute emergence. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 2, pp.302-11.
@

Pap, A.

(1951): Other minds and the principle of verifiability. In: ' Revue Internationale de Philosophie', vol. 5, pp.280-306.
@

Pap, A.

(1952): Semantic analysis and psychophysical dualism. In: '1952 '.
@

Papineau, D.

(1984): Representation and explanation. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 51, pp.550-72.
@

Papineau, D.

(1985): Social facts and psychological facts. In: G. Currie; A. Musgrave (Ed.): 'Popper and the Human Sciences'. Martinus Nijhoff.
@

Papineau, D.

(1989): Why supervenience?. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 50, pp.66-71.
@

Papineau, D.

(1990): Truth and teleology. In: D. Knowles (Ed.): ' Explanation and its Limits'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Papineau, D.

(1991): Teleology and mental states. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 65.
@

Papineau, D.

(1992): Irreducibility and teleology. In: D. Charles; K. Lennon (Ed.): 'Reduction, Explanation and Realism'. Oxford University Press.
@

Papineau, D.

(1994): Philosophical Naturalism. Blackwell.
@

Papineau, D.

(1995): Arguments for supervenience and physical realization. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Papineau, D.

(1995): Mind, health, and biological purpose. In: A. Griffiths (Ed.): 'Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychiatry'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Papineau, D.

(1996): Doubtful intuitions. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 11, pp.130-32.
@

Papineau, D.

(1998): Teleosemantics and indeterminacy. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 76, pp.1-14.
@

Papineau, D.

(1999): Normativity and judgment. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 73, pp.16-43.
@

Papineau, D.

(2001): The status of teleosemantics, or how to stop worrying about Swampman . In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 79, pp.279-89.
@

Papineau, D.

(2001): The rise of physicalism. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): ' Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Papineau, D.

(2003): The Roots of Reason: Philosophical Essays on Rationality, Evolution, and Probability. Oxford University Press.
@

Papineau, D.; Huttemann, A.

(2005): Physicalism decomposed. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 65, pp.33-39.
@

Parfit, D.

(1971): Personal identity. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 80, pp.3-27.
@

Parfit, D.

(1971): On the importance of self-identity. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 68, pp.683-90.
@

Parfit, D.

(1973): Later selves and moral principles. In: A. Montefiore (Ed.): ' Philosophy and Personal Relations'. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
@

Parfit, D.

(1976): Lewis, Perry, and what matters. In: A. Rorty (Ed.): ' The Identities of Persons'. University of California Press.
@

Parfit, D.

(1982): Personal identity and rationality. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 53.
@

Parfit, D.

(1984): Reasons and Persons. Oxford University Press.
@

Parfit, D.

(1987): Divided minds and the nature of persons. In: C. Blakemore; S. Greenfield (Ed.): 'Mindwaves'. Blackwell.
@

Parfit, D.

(1995): The unimportance of identity. In: H. Harris (Ed.): 'Identity '. Oxford University Press.
@

Parfit, D.

(1999): Experiences, subjects, and conceptual schemes. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 26, pp.217-70.
@

Pargetter, R.

(1984): The scientific inference to other minds. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 62, pp.158-63.
@

Park, S.

(1994): Reinterpreting Ryle: A nonbehaviorist analysis. In: ' Journal of the History of Philosophy', vol. 32, pp.265-90.
@

Parkinson, B.

(2004): Unpicking reasonable emotions. In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): 'Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality'. Oxford University Press.
@

Parnas, J.

(2004): Belief and pathology of self-awareness: A phenomenological contribution to the classification of delusions. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 11.
@

Parrett, H.

(1983): On Believing. De Gruyter.
@

Parsell, M.

(2005): Context-sensitive inference, modularity, and the assumption of formal processing. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 18, pp.45-58.
@

Partridge, D.; Wilks, Y.

(1990): The Foundations of Artificial Intelligence: A Sourcebook . Cambridge University Press.
@

Patten, D.

(2003): How do we deceive ourselves. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 16, pp.229-247.
@

Patterson, S.

(1990): The explanatory role of belief ascriptions. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 59, pp.313-32.
@

Patterson, S.

(1991): Individualism and semantic development. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 58, pp.15-35.
@

Patterson, S.

(1996): Success-orientation and individualism in the theory of vision. In: K. Akins (Ed.): 'Perception'. Oxford University Press.
@

Patterson, S. A.

(1996): The anomalism of psychology. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 96, pp.37-52.
@

Paull, R. C.; Sider, T. R.

(1992): In defense of global supervenience. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 52, pp.833-53.
@

Peacocke, A.; Gillett, G.

(1987): Persons and Personality: A Contemporary Inquiry. Blackwell.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1979): Argument for token identity. In: 'Holistic Explanation '.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1983): Between instrumentalism and brain-writing. In: ' Sense and Content'.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1984): Consciousness and other minds. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 58, pp.97-117.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1986): Thoughts: An Essay on Content. Blackwell.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1986): Explanation in computational psychology: Language, perception and level 1.5. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 1, pp.101-23.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1989): What are concepts?. In: 'Midwest Studies of Philosophy ', vol. 14.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1989): Possession conditions: A focal point for theories of concepts. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 4, pp.51-56.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1991): Content and norms in a natural world. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Information, Semantics, and Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1991): The metaphysics of concepts. In: 'Mind ', vol. 100, pp.525-46.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1992): A Study of Concepts. MIT Press.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1993): Externalist explanation. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 67, pp.203-30.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1995): Content, computation, and externalism. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Content'. Ridgeview.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1996): Entitlement, self-knowledge, and conceptual redeployment. In: 'Proceedings of the Aristotelian Sociey', vol. 96, pp.117-58.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1996): Precis of A Study of Concepts. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.407-52.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1996): Can a theory of concepts explain the a priori: A reply to Skorupski . In: 'International Journal of Philosophical Studies', vol. 4, pp.154-60.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1996): The relation between philosophical and psychological theories of concepts. In: P. Millican; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Machines and Thought'. Oxford University Press.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1996): Our entitlement to self-knowledge: Entitlement, self-knowledge, and conceptual redeployment. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 96, pp.117-58.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1998): Free will. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Peacocke, C.

(1999): Computation as involving content: A response to Egan. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 14, pp.195-202.
@

Peacocke, C.

(2000): Theories of concepts: A wider task. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 8, pp.298-321.
@

Peacocke, C.

(2001): First-person reference, representational independence, and self-knowledge. In: A. Brook; R. DeVidi (Ed.): ' Self-Reference and Self-Awareness'. John Benjamins.
@

Peacocke, C.

(2003): Implicit conceptions, understanding, and rationality. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Peacocke, C.

(2004): Interrelations: Concepts, knowledge, reference and structure. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.85-98.
@

Peacocke, C.

(2005): Rationale and maxims in the study of concepts. In: ' Nous', vol. 39, pp.167-78.
@

Peacocke, C.

(2005): Joint attention: Its nature, reflexivity, and relation to common knowledge. In: N. Eilan; C. Hoerl; T. McCormack; J. Roessler (Ed.): 'Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Pelletier, J.

(2002): Reply to 'Varieties of simulation'. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Penco, C.

(2002): Holism, strawberries, and hair dryers. In: 'Topoi ', vol. 21, pp.47-54.
@

Penelhum, T.

(1959): Personal identity, memory, and survival. In: '1959 '.
@

Penelhum, T.

(1971): The importance of self-identity. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 68, pp.667-78.
@

Penrose, R.

(1989): The Emperor's New Mind. Oxford University Press.
@

Penrose, R.

(1990): Precis of The Emperor's New Mind. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 13, pp.643-705.
@

Penrose, R.

(1992): Setting the scene: The claim and the issues. In: D. Broadbent (Ed.): 'The Simulation of Human Intelligence'. Blackwell.
@

Penrose, R.

(1994): Shadows of the Mind. Oxford University Press.
@

Penrose, R.

(1996): Beyond the doubting of a shadow. In: 'Psyche ', vol. 2, pp.89-129.
@

Penrose, R.

(2003): Consciousness, computation, and the Chinese room. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Pepper, S.

(1975): A split in the identity theory. In: C. Cheng (Ed.): ' Philosophical Aspects of the Mind-Body Problem'. Hawaii University Press.
@

Pepper, S. C.

(1926): Emergence. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp.241-45.
@

Pereboom, D.

(1991): Why a scientific realist cannot be a functionalist. In: 'Synthese', vol. 88, pp.341-58.
@

Pereboom, D.

(1995): Conceptual structure and the individuation of content. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.401-428.
@

Pereboom, D.

(1995): Determinism al dente. In: 'Nous ', vol. 29, pp.21-45.
@

Pereboom, D.

(2000): Alternative possibilities and causal histories. In: ' Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.119-138.
@

Pereboom, D.

(2001): Living without Free Will. Cambridge University Press.
@

Pereboom, D.

(2002): Robust nonreductive materialism. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 99, pp.499-531.
@

Pereboom, D.

(2002): Living without free will: The case for hard incompatibilism. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Pereboom, D.; Kornblith, H.

(1991): The metaphysics of irreducibility. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 63, pp.125-45.
@

Perkins, R. K.

(1973): Russell on memory. In: 'Mind', vol. 82, pp.600-1.
@

Perlis, D.

(1991): Putting one's foot in one's head -- Part 1: Why. In: ' Nous', vol. 25, pp.435-55.
@

Perlis, D.

(1994): Putting one's foot in one's head -- Part 2: How. In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): 'Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons'. Academic Press.
@

Perlman, M.

(1997): The trouble with two-factor conceptual role theories. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 7, pp.495-513.
@

Perlman, M.

(2000): Conceptual Flux: Mental Representation, Misrepresentation, and Concept Change. Kluwer.
@

Perlman, M.

(2002): Pagan teleology: Adaptational role and the philosophy of mind. In: A. Ariew (Ed.): 'Functions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Perner, J.

(1994): The necessity and impossibility of simulation. In: C. Peacocke (Ed.): 'Objectivity, Simulation, and the Unity of Consciousness'. Oxford University Press.
@

Perner, J.

(1996): Simulation as explicitation of predication-implicit knowledge about the mind: Arguments for a simulation-theory mix . In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Perner, J.; Gschaider, A.; Kuhberger, A.; Schrofner, S.

(1999): Predicting others through simulation or by theory? A method to decide. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 14, pp.57-79.
@

Perrett, R. W.; Barton, C.

(1999): Personal identity, reductionism, and the necessity of origins. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 51, pp.277-94.
@

Perry, J.

(1972): Can the self divide?. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 69, pp.463-88.
@

Perry, J.

(1975): Personal Identity. University of California Press.
@

Perry, J.

(1975): Personal identity, memory, and the problem of circularity. In: J. Perry (Ed.): 'Personal Identity'. University of California Press.
@

Perry, J.

(1976): The importance of being identical. In: A. Rorty (Ed.): ' The Identities of Persons'. University of California Press.
@

Perry, J.

(1978): A Dialogue on Personal Identity and Immortality. Hackett.
@

Perry, J.

(1979): The problem of the essential indexical. In: 'Nous ', vol. 13, pp.3-21.
@

Perry, J.

(1994): Fodor and Lepore on holism. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 73, pp.123-58.
@

Perry, J.; Israel, D.

(1991): Fodor and psychological explanation. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Persson, I.

(2004): Self-doubt: Why we are not identical to things of any kind. In: 'Ratio', vol. 17, pp.390-408.
@

Persson, S.

(2003): Colours with a Humean face. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 4.
@

Perszyk, K. J.

(1999): Compatibilism and the free will defence: A reply to Bishop. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosopy', vol. 77, pp.92-105.
@

Peruzzi, A.

(2004): Mind and Causality. John Benjamins.
@

Pessin, A.

(1995): Mentalese syntax: Between a rock and two hard places. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 78, pp.33-53.
@

Peters, S. L.

(1995): Emergent Materialism: A Proposed Solution to the Mind-Body Problem . University Press of America.
@

Peterson, J.

(1985): Persons and the problem of interaction. In: ' Modern Schoolman', vol. 62, pp.131-38.
@

Petrie, B.

(1987): Global supervenience and reduction. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 48, pp.119-30.
@

Petrie, B.

(1990): Nonautonomous psychology. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 28, pp.539-59.
@

Pettit, P.

(1986): Broad-minded explanation and psychology. In: P. Pettit; J. McDowell (Ed.): 'Subject, Thought and Context'. Oxford University Press.
@

Pettit, P.

(1990): The reality of rule-following. In: 'Mind ', vol. 99, pp.1-21.
@

Pettit, P.

(1992): The nature of naturalism. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 66, pp.245-66.
@

Pettit, P.

(1993): A definition of physicalism. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 53, pp.213-23.
@

Pettit, P.

(1993): A definition of physicalism. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 53, pp.213-23.
@

Pettit, P.

(1994): Microphysicalism without contingent micro-macro laws. In: 'Analysis', vol. 54, pp.253-57.
@

Pettit, P.

(1995): Microphysicalism, dottism, and reduction. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 55, pp.141-46.
@

Pettit, P.

(2000): How the folk understand folk psychology. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 14, pp.26-38.
@

Pettit, P.; Price, H.

(1989): Bare functional desire. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 49, pp.162-69.
@

Pfeifer, K.

(1992): Searle, strong AI, and two ways of sorting cucumbers. In: 'Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 17, pp.347-50.
@

Philips, J.; Morley, J.

(2003): Imagination and its Pathologies. MIT Press.
@

Phillips, H.

(1995): Vicissitudes of the I: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind . Prentice-Hall.
@

Piattelli-Palmarini, M.

(1980): Language and Learning: The Debate Between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky. Harvard University Press.
@

Piattelli-Palmarini, M.

(1986): The rise of selective theories: A case study and some lessons from immunology. In: W. Demopoulos (Ed.): ' Language Learning and Concept Acquisition'. Ablex.
@

Piattelli-Palmarini, M.

(1989): Evolution, selection, and cognition: From learning to parameter setting in biology and in the study of language. In: 'Cognition', vol. 31, pp.1-44.
@

Piccinini, G.

(2000): Turing's rules for the imitation game. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 10, pp.573-582.
@

Piccinini, G.

(2003): Alan Turing and the mathematical objection. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 13, pp.23-48.
@

Piccinini, G.

(2004): Functionalism, computationalism, and mental contents. In: '2004'.
@

Piccinini, G.

(2004): Functionalism, computationalism, and mental states. In: 'Studies in History and Philosophy of Science', vol. 35.
@

Pickard, H.

(2003): Emotions and the problem of other minds. In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Pickering, M.; Chater, N.

(1995): Why cognitive science is not formalized folk psychology . In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 5.
@

Pickles, D.

(1989): Intentionality, representation, and function. In: ' Sussex University, Cognitive Science Research Paper', vol. 140.
@

Pietroski, P. M.

(1994): Mental causation for dualists. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.336-66.
@

Pietroski, P.; Menzies, P.

(2003): Causing actions. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp.440-446.
@

Pietroski, P.; Rey, G.

(1995): When other things aren't equal: Saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 46, pp.81-110.
@

Pietrowski, P. M.

(1992): Intentionality and teleological error. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 73, pp.267-82.
@

Pihlstrom, S.

(1999): What shall we do with emergence? A survey of a fundamenta; issue in the metaphysics and epistemology of science. In: 'South African Journal of Philosophy', vol. 18, pp.192-210.
@

Pineda, D.

(2001): Functionalism and nonreductive physicalism. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 16, pp.43-63.
@

Pinker, S.

(2005): So how does the mind work? Mind and Language, vol. 20, pp.1-38.
@

Pinker, S.; Bloom, P.

(1990): Natural language and natural selection. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 13, pp.707-27.
@

Pinker, S.; Prince, A.

(1988): On language and connectionism. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 28, pp.73-193.
@

Pitcher, G.

(1960): Sensations and brain processes: A reply to Professor Smart. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 38, pp.150-7.
@

Pitcher, G.

(1970): The awfulness of pain. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 48.
@

Pitcher, G.

(1970): Pain perception. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 74, pp.368-93.
@

Pitt, D.

(1999): In defense of definitions. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 12, pp.139-156.
@

Pitt, D.

(2000): Nativism and the theory of content. In: 'Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp.222-239.
@

Place, U. T.

(1956): Is consciousness a brain process?. In: ' British Journal of Psychology', vol. 47, pp.44-50.
@

Place, U. T.

(1960): Materialism as a scientific hypothesis. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 69, pp.101-4.
@

Place, U. T.

(1972): Sensations and processes: A reply to Munsat. In: '1972 '.
@

Place, U. T.

(1988): Thirty years on -- Is consciousness still a brain process?. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 66, pp.208-19.
@

Place, U. T.

(1989): Low claim assertions. In: J. Heil (Ed.): ' Cause, Mind, and Reality: Essays Honoring C. B. Martin'. Kluwer.
@

Place, U. T.

(1989): Toward a connectionist version of the causal theory of reference . In: 'Acta Analytica', vol. 4, pp.71-97.
@

Place, U. T.

(1992): Eliminative connectionism: Its implications for a return to an empiricist/behaviorist linguistics. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.21-35.
@

Place, U. T.

(1993): A radical behaviorist methodology for the empirical investigation of private events. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.25-35.
@

Place, U. T.

(1996): Inentionality as the mark of the dispositional. In: ' Dialectica', vol. 50, pp.91-120.
@

Place, U. T.

(1996): Folk psychology from the standpoint of conceptual analysis. In: W. O'Donahue; R. Kitchener (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of Psychology'. Sage Publications.
@

Place, U. T.

(1999): Intentionality and the physical: A reply to Mumford. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.225-30.
@

Place, U. T.

(2000): The two-factor theory of the mind-brain relation. In: ' Brain and Mind', vol. 1, pp.29-43.
@

Place, U. T.

(2003): Identifying the Mind: Selected Papers of U. T. Place. Oxford University Press.
@

Plantinga, A.

(1966): Induction and other minds. In: 'Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 19, pp.441-61.
@

Plantinga, A.

(1967): God and Other Minds. Cornell University Press.
@

Plantinga, A.

(1968): Induction and other minds II. In: ' Review of Metaphysics', vol. 12, pp.524-33.
@

Plantinga, A.

(2004): Evolution, epiphenomenalism, reductionism. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 68, pp.602-619.
@

Plotkin, H.

(2001): Evolution and the human mind: How far can we go?. In: D. Walsh (Ed.): 'Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Pluhar, E.

(1978): Emergence and reduction. In: ' Studies in History and Philosophy of Science', vol. 9, pp.279-89.
@

Plunkett, K.

(2001): Connectionism today. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 129, pp.185-194.
@

Pogue, J. E.

(1993): Identity, survival, and the reasonableness of replication. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 31, pp.45-70.
@

Pojman, L. P.

(1985): Believing and willing. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 15, pp.37-56.
@

Poland, J.

(1994): Physicalism: The Empirical Foundations. Oxford University Press.
@

Poland, J.; von Eckardt, B.; Spaulding, W.

(1994): Problems with the DSM approach to classifying psychopathology. In: G. Graham; L. Stephens (Ed.): ' Philosophical Psychopathology'. MIT Press.
@

Polger, T.

(2002): Putnam's intuition. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 109, pp.143-70.
@

Pollack, J. B.

(1990): Recursive distributed representations. In: ' Artificial Intelligence', vol. 46, pp.77-105.
@

Pollock, J.

(1989): How to Build a Person: A Prolegomenon. MIT Press.
@

Pollock, J.

(1990): Understanding the language of thought. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 58, pp.95-120.
@

Pollock, JL.

(1997): Reasoning about change and persistence: A solution to the frame problem . In: 'Nous', vol. 31, pp.143-169.
@

Popper, K.

(1983): Is determinism self-refuting?. In: 'Mind ', vol. 92, pp.103-4.
@

Popper, K. R.

(1953): Language and the body-mind problem: A restatement of interactionism . In: 'In <i>Proceedings of the', vol. 11.
@

Popper, K. R.

(1955): A note on the body-mind problem. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 15, pp.131-35.
@

Possin, K.

(1986): The case against Stich's Syntactic Theory of Mind. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 49, pp.405-18.
@

Post, J.

(2001): Sense and supervenience. In: 'Philo ', vol. 4, pp.123-137.
@

Post, J. F.

(1984): On the determinacy of valuation. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 45, pp.315-33.
@

Post, J. F.

(1995): "Global" supervenient determination: Too permissive?. In: E. Savellos; U. Yalcin (Ed.): 'Supervenience: New Essays'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Povinelli, D.

(2000): Folk Physics for Apes: The Chimpanzee's Theory of How the World Works . Oxford University Press.
@

Povinelli, D.; Vonk, J.

(2004): We don't need a microscope to explore the chimpanzee's mind . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.1-28.
@

Pratt, I.

(1993): Analysis and the attitudes. In: S. Wagner; R. Warner (Ed.): ' Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal'. University of Notre Dame Press.
@

Pratt, I.

(1996): Encoding psychological knowledge. In: P. Millican; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Machines and Thought'. Oxford University Press.
@

Premack, D.

(1986): Gavagai! or the Future History of the Animal Language Controversy . MIT Press.
@

Premack, D.; Woodruff, G.

(1978): Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?. In: 'Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 4, pp.515-629.
@

Presley, C. P.

(1967): The Identity Theory of Mind. University of Queensland Press.
@

Preston, B.

(1991): AI, anthropocentrism, and the evolution of "intelligence.". In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 1, pp.259-277.
@

Preston, B.

(1993): Heidegger and artificial intelligence. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 53, pp.43-69.
@

Preston, B.

(1994): Behaviorism and mentalism: Is there a third alternative?. In: 'Synthese', vol. 100, pp.167-96.
@

Preston, B.

(1995): The ontological argument against the mind-machine hypothesis. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 80, pp.131-57.
@

Preston, J. M.

(1989): Folk psychology as theory or practice? The case for eliminative materialism. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 32, pp.277-303.
@

Preston, J.; Bishop, M.

(2002): Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence. Oxford University Press.
@

Preti, C.

(2000): Belief and desire under the elms. In: 'Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp.270-284.
@

Preti, C.

(2002): Normativity and meaning: Kripke's skeptical paradox reconsidered. In: 'Philosophical Forum', vol. 33, pp.39-62.
@

Preyer, G.

(2000): Primary reasons: From radical interpretation to a pure anomalism of the mental. In: 'Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp.158-179.
@

Price, C.

(2001): Functions in Mind: A Theory of Intentional Content. Oxford University Press.
@

Price, H.

(1989): Defending desire-as-belief. In: 'Mind ', vol. 98, pp.119-27.
@

Price, H.

(1995): Psychology in perspective. In: M. Michael; J. O'Leary-Hawthorne (Ed.): 'Philosophy in Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Price, H. H.

(1938): Our evidence for the existence of other minds. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 13, pp.425-56.
@

Price, H. H.

(1960): Some objections to behaviorism. In: S. Hook (Ed.): ' Dimensions of Mind'. New York University Press.
@

Priest, G.

(1994): Godel's theorem and the mind... again. In: M. Michael; J. O'Leary-Hawthorne (Ed.): 'Philosophy in Mind: The Place of Philosophy in the Study of Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Priest, G.

(2000): Objects of thought. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 78, pp.494-502.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2000): The duality of content. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 100, pp.1-34.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2002): Furnishing the Mind: Concepts and Their Perceptual Basis. MIT Press.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2002): Consciousness, computation, and emotion. In: S. Moore; M. Oaksford (Ed.): 'Consciousness, Emotional Self-Regulation and the Brain'. John Benjamins.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2003): Level-headed mysterianism and artificial experience. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 10.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2003): Emotions, psychosemantics, and embodied appraisals. In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2004): Sensible ideas: A reply to Markman and Stilwell and Sarnecki. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 17, pp.419-30.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2004): Which emotions are basic?. In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): ' Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality'. Oxford University Press.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2004): Embodied emotions. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Prinz, J. J.

(2004): Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of the Emotions. Oxford University Press.
@

Prinz, J. J.; Clark, A.

(2004): Putting concepts to work: Some thoughts for the Twentyfirst Century. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 19, pp.57-69.
@

Pritchard, D.

(2002): McKinsey paradoxes, radical skepticism, and the transmission of knowledge across known entailments. In: 'Synthese', vol. 130, pp.279-302.
@

Pritchard, D.; Kallestrup, J.

(2004): An argument for the inconsistency of content externalism and epistemic internalism. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 2004.
@

Proudfoot, D.

(2003): Wittgenstein's anticipation of the Chinese room. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Proudfoot, D.

(2004): The implications of an externalist theory of rule-following behavior for robot cognition. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 14, pp.283-308.
@

Proust, J.

(1999): Mind, space and objectivity in non-human animals. In: ' Erkenntnis', vol. 51, pp.545-562.
@

Proust, J.

(2002): Can 'radical' simulation theories explain psychological concept acquisition?. In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Pryor, J.

(1999): Immunity to error through misidentification. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 26, pp.271-304.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1966): Can humans think?. In: '1966'.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1967): On thinking machines and feeling machines. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 18, pp.39-51.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1973): Brain bisection and personal identity. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 24, pp.339-55.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1973): Multiple identity. In: 'Personalist ', vol. 54, pp.203-13.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1975): The mute self: A reaction to DeWitt's alternative account of the split-brain data. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 27, pp.65-73.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1975): Is pain necessary?. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 50, pp.259-69.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1978): The refutation of materialism. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 8, pp.157-62.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1981): The case for mental duality: Evidence from split-brain data and other considerations. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 4, pp.93-123.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1989): Two brains, two minds. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 40, pp.137-44.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1993): Mind with a double brain. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 44, pp.675-92.
@

Puccetti, R.

(1993): Dennett on the split-brain. In: 'Psycoloquy ', vol. 4, no.52.
@

Pugmire, D.

(1994): Real emotion. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 54, pp.105-22.
@

Puhl, K. (ed.)

(1991): Meaning Scepticism. de Gruyter.
@

Purthill, R.

(1971): Beating the imitation game. In: 'Mind ', vol. 80, pp.290-94.
@

Pust, J.

(1999): External accounts of folk psychology, eliminativism, and the simulation theory. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 14, pp.113-130.
@

Putnam, H,

(1985): Why reason can't be naturalized. In: 'Realism and Reason '.
@

Putnam, H.

(1960): Minds and machines. In: S. Hook (Ed.): 'Dimensions of Mind '. New York University Press.
@

Putnam, H.

(1962): Dreaming and `depth grammar'. In: R. Butler (Ed.): ' Analytical Philosophy: First Series'. Oxford University Press.
@

Putnam, H.

(1963): Brains and behavior. In: R. Butler (Ed.): ' Analytical Philosophy: Second Series'. Blackwell.
@

Putnam, H.

(1964): Robots: machines or artificially created life?. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 61, pp.668-91.
@

Putnam, H.

(1967): The nature of mental states. In: Capitan; Merrill (Ed.): ' Art, Mind, and Religion'. Pittsburgh University Press.
@

Putnam, H.

(1967): The mental life of some machines. In: H. Castaneda (Ed.): ' Intentionality, Minds and Perception'. Wayne State University Press.
@

Putnam, H.

(1967): The mental life of some machines. In: H. Castaneda (Ed.): ' Intentionality, Minds and Perception'. Wayne State University Press.
@

Putnam, H.

(1967): The `Innateness Hypothesis' and explanatory models in linguistics . In: 'Synthese', vol. 17, pp.12-22.
@

Putnam, H.

(1974): Reductionism and the nature of psychology. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 2, pp.131-46.
@

Putnam, H.

(1975): The meaning of `meaning'. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 7, pp.131-193.
@

Putnam, H.

(1975): Philosophy and our mental life. In: ' Mind, Language, and Reality'.
@

Putnam, H.

(1980): What is innate and why. In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): ' Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky'. Harvard University Press.
@

Putnam, H.

(1980): Comments on Chomsky's and Fodor's replies. In: M. Piattelli-Palmarini (Ed.): 'Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky'. Harvard University Press.
@

Putnam, H.

(1983): Analyticity and apriority: Beyond Wittgenstein and Quine. In: 'Realism and Reason: Philosophical Papers, Volume 3'.
@

Putnam, H.

(1985): Reflexive reflections. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 22, pp.143-153.
@

Putnam, H.

(1987): Meaning, other people, and the world. In: ' Representation and Reality'.
@

Putnam, H.

(1987): Fodor and Block on narrow content. In: ' Representation and Reality'.
@

Putnam, H.

(1987): Representation and Reality. MIT Press.
@

Putnam, H.

(1996): On Wittgenstein's philosophy of mathematics. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume', vol. 70, pp.243-264.
@

Putnam, H.

(2000): The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body and World. Columbia University Press.
@

Pylyshyn, Z.

(1999): Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 22, pp.341-365.
@

Pylyshyn, Z.

(2002): Mental imagery: In search of a theory. In: ' The Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 25, pp.157-182.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1973): What the mind's eye tells the mind's brain: A critique of mental imagery. In: 'Psych Bull ', vol. 80, pp.1-24.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1978): Computational models and empirical constraints. In: 'Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 1, pp.98-128.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1978): Imagery and artificial intelligence. In: W. Savage (Ed.): 'Perception and Cognition'. University of Minnesota Press.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1979): Complexity and the study of artificial and human intelligence . In: M. Ringle (Ed.): 'Philosophical Perspectives in Artificial Intelligence'. Humanities Press.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1980): Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundation of cognitive science. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 3, pp.111-32.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1981): The imagery debate: Analog media vs. tacit knowledge. In: 'Psychological Review', vol. 88, pp.16-45.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1984): Computation and Cognition. MIT Press.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1987): What's in a mind?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 70, pp.97-122.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1987): What's in a mind?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 70, pp.97-122.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1987): The Robot's Dilemma. Ablex.
@

Pylyshyn, Z. W.

(1989): Computing and cognitive science. In: M. Posner (Ed.): ' Foundations of Cognitive Science'. MIT Press.

Q


@

Quartz, S.

(2003): Innateness and the brain. In: 'Biology and Philosophy ', vol. 18, pp.13-40.
@

Quesada, D.

(2003): Basic self-knowledge and externalism. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Quillen, K.

(1986): Propositional attitudes and psychological explanation. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 1, pp.133-57.
@

Quine, W. V.

(1966): On mental entities. In: 'The Ways of Paradox'.
@

Quine, W. V.

(1975): Mind and verbal dispositions. In: Guttenplan (Ed.): ' Mind and Language'. Oxford University Press.
@

Quine, W. V.

(1980): Sellars on behaviorism, language, and meaning. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 61, pp.26-30.
@

Quine, W. V.

(1985): States of mind. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 82, pp.5-8.
@

Quinn, W.

(1968): Pleasure -- disposition or episode?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 28, pp.578-86.

R


@

Raatikainen, P.

(2002): McCall's Godelian argument is invalid. In: ' Facta Philosophica', vol. 4, pp.167-69.
@

Rachels, S.

(2000): Is unpleasantness intrinsic to unpleasant experiences?. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 99, pp.187-210.
@

Rachlin, H.

(1985): Pain and behavior. In: 'Behavioral and Brain Sciences ', vol. 8, pp.43-83.
@

Radcliffe Richards, J.

(2000): Human Nature after Darwin: A Philosophical Introduction . Routledge.
@

Radden, J.

(1996): Divided Minds and Successive Selves: Ethical Issues in Disorders of Identity and Personality. MIT Press.
@

Radden, J.

(2004): The Philosophy of Psychiatry: A Companion. Oxford University Press.
@

Radner, D.

(1993): Directed action and animal communication. In: 'Ration ', vol. 6, pp.135-54.
@

Radner, D.

(1999): Mind and function in animal communication. In: ' Erkenntnis', vol. 51, pp.633-648.
@

Radner, D.; Radner, M.

(1995): Cognition, natural selection, and the intentional stance . In: 'International Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 9, pp.109-19.
@

Raffman, D.

(1998): First-person authority and the internal reality of beliefs. In: C. Wright; B. Smith; C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Rakover, S.

(1983): In defense of memory viewed as stored mental representation. In: 'Behaviorism', vol. 11, pp.53-62.
@

Ramsey, W.

(1990): Where does the self-refutation objection take us?. In: ' Inquiry', vol. 33, pp.453-65.
@

Ramsey, W.

(1992): Prototypes and conceptual analysis. In: 'Topoi ', vol. 11, pp.59-70.
@

Ramsey, W.

(1994): Distributed representation and causal modularity: A rejoinder to Forster and Saidel. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.453-61.
@

Ramsey, W.

(1995): Rethinking distributed representation. In: ' Acta Analytica', vol. 10, pp.9-25.
@

Ramsey, W.

(1997): Do connectionist representations earn their explanatory keep?. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.34-66.
@

Ramsey, W.; Stich, S. P.

(1990): Connectionism and three levels of nativism. In: 'Synthese', vol. 82, pp.177-205.
@

Ramsey, W.; Stich, S. P.

(1990): Connectionism and three levels of nativism. In: 'Synthese', vol. 82, pp.177-205.
@

Ramsey, W.; Stich, S. P.; Garon, J.

(1991): Connectionism, eliminativism, and the future of folk psychology. In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Ramsey, W.; Stich, S. P.; Garon, J.

(1991): Connectionism, eliminativism and the future of folk psychology. In: W. Ramsey; S. Stich; D. Rumelhart (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Connectionist Theory'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Ramsey, W.; Stich, S. P.; Rumelhart, D. M.

(1991): Philosophy and Connectionist Theory . Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Rankin, T. L.

(1987): The Turing paradigm: A critical assessment. In: ' Dialogue', vol. 29, pp.50-55.
@

Rantala, V.; Vaden, T.

(1997): Minds as connoting systems: Logic and the language of thought . In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 46, pp.315-334.
@

Rapaport, W.

(1984): Searle's experiments with thought. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 53, pp.271-9.
@

Rapaport, W.

(1993): Because mere calculating isn't thinking: Comments on Hauser's "Why isn't my pocket calculator a thinking thing?" . In: 'Minds and machines', vol. 3, pp.11-20.
@

Rapaport, W. J.

(1988): Syntactic semantics: Foundations of computational natural language understanding. In: J. Fetzer (Ed.): ' Aspects of AI'. Kluwer.
@

Rapaport, W. J.

(1995): Understanding understanding: Syntactic semantics and computational cognition. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.49-88.
@

Ratcliffe, M.

(2001): A Kantian stance on the intentional stance. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 16, pp.29-52.
@

Ravenscroft, I.

(1997): Physical properties. In: ' Southern Journal Of Philosophy', vol. 35, pp.419-431.
@

Ravenscroft, I.

(1998): Neuroscience and the mind. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp.132-137.
@

Ravenscroft, I.

(2003): Simulation, collapse and Humean motivation. Mind and Language 18:162-174. Recanati, F. 2002. Varieties of simulation . In: J. Dokic; J. Proust (Ed.): 'Simulation and Knowledge of Action'. John Benjamins.
@

Ravizza, M.

(1994): Semi-compatibilism and the transfer of non-responsibility. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 75, pp.61-93.
@

Ray, G.

(1997): Fodor and the inscrutability problem. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp.475-89.
@

Raymont, P.

(2001): Are mental properties causally relevant?. In: 'Dialogue ', vol. 40, pp.509-528.
@

Raymont, P.

(2003): Kim on closure, exclusion, and nonreductive physicalism. In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Rea, M.; Silver, D.

(2000): Personal identity and psychological continuity. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 61, pp.185-194.
@

Read, R.

(1995): The unstatability of Kripkean scepticism. In: ' Philosophical Papers', vol. 24, pp.67-74.
@

Read, R.

(2000): What 'There can be no such thing as meaning anything by any word' could possibly mean. In: A. Crary; R. Read (Ed.): 'The New Wittgenstein'. Routledge.
@

Recanati, F.

(1990): Externalism and narrow content. In: '1990'.
@

Recanati, F.

(1994): How narrow is narrow content?. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 48, pp.209-29.
@

Recanati, F.

(1997): Can we believe what we do not understand?. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 12, pp.84-100.
@

Recanati, F.

(2002): The Fodorian fallacy. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 72, pp.285-89.
@

Redhead, M.

(2004): Mathematics and the mind. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 55.
@

Reiner, R.

(1995): Arguments against the possibility of perfect rationality. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.373-89.
@

Reisberg, D.; Chambers, D.

(1991): Neither pictures nor propositions: What can we learn from a mental image?. In: ' Canadian Journal of Psychology', vol. 45, pp.336-52.
@

Rensselaer Wilson, van, H.

(1955): Causal discontinuity in fatalism and indeterminism . In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 52, pp.134-58.
@

Reppert, V.

(1991): Ramsey on eliminativism and self-refutation. In: ' Inquiry', vol. 34, pp.499-508.
@

Reppert, V.

(1992): Eliminative materialism, cognitive suicide, and begging the question . In: 'Metaphilosophy', vol. 23, pp.378-92.
@

Resnick, P.

(1994): Intentionality is phlogiston. In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): ' Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons'. Academic Press.
@

Resnik, D.

(2000): Pain as a folk psychological concept: A clinical perspective. In: 'Brain and Mind', vol. 1, pp.193-207.
@

Revonsuo, A.

(2001): On the nature of explanation in the neurosciences. In: P. Machamer; P. McLaughlin; R. Grush (Ed.): 'Theory and Method in the Neurosciences'. University of Pittsburgh wPress.
@

Revonsuo, A.; Tarkko, K.

(2002): Binding in dreams: The bizarreness of dream images and the unity of consciousness. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 9, pp.3-24.
@

Rey, G.

(1976): Survival. In: A. Rorty (Ed.): 'The Identities of Persons'. University of California Press.
@

Rey, G.

(1980): Functionalism and the emotions. In (A. Rorty, ed), Explaining Emotions . In: '1980'.
@

Rey, G.

(1981): What are mental images?. In: N. Block (Ed.): ' Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology'. @

Rey, G.

(1983): Concepts and stereotypes. In: 'Cognition', vol. 15, pp.237-62.
@

Rey, G.

(1986): What's really going on in Searle's `Chinese Room'. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 50, pp.169-85.
@

Rey, G.

(1991): An explanatory budget for connectionism and eliminativism. In: T. Horgan; J. Tienson (Ed.): 'Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind'. Kluwer.
@

Rey, G.

(1992): Semantic externalism and conceptual competence. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 66, pp.315-33.
@

Rey, G.

(1995): A not "merely empirical" argument for the language of thought. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.201-22.
@

Rey, G.

(1997): Contemporary Philosophy of Mind: A Contentiously Classical Approach. Blackwell.
@

Rey, G.

(2001): Physicalism and psychology: A plea for a substantive philosophy of mind . In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Rey, G.

(2003): Searle's misunderstandings of functionalism and strong AI. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Rey, G.

(2004): Fodor's ingratitude and change of heart?. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.70-84.
@

Rhees, R.

(1954): Can there be a private language?. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume', vol. 28.
@

Ribes-Inesta, E.

(2004): Behavior is abstraction, not ostension: Conceptual and historical remarks on the nature of psychology. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 32, pp.55-68.
@

Richard, M.

(1995): What isn't a belief?. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 22, pp.291-318.
@

Richards, G.

(1996): On the necessary survival of folk psychology. In: W. O'Donahue; R. Kitchener (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of Psychology'. Sage Publications.
@

Richardson, A.

(1969): Mental Imagery. Routledge.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1979): Functionalism and reductionism. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 46, pp.533-58.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1979): Functionalism and reductionism. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 46, pp.533-58.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1980): Intentional realism or intentional instrumentalism?. In: 'Cognition and Brain Theory', vol. 3, pp.125-35.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1981): Internal representation: Prologue to a theory of intentionality . In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 12, pp.171-212.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1981): Disappearance and the identity theory. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 11, pp.473-85.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1982): How not to reduce a functional psychology. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 49, pp.125-37.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1982): The `scandal' of Cartesian dualism. In: 'Mind ', vol. 91, pp.20-37.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1982): Turing tests for intelligence: Ned Block's defense of psychologism . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 41, pp.421-6.
@

Richardson, R. C.

(1999): Cognitive science and neuroscience: New wave reductionism. In: 'Philosopical Psychology', vol. 12, pp.297-307.
@

Rieber, S.

(1998): The concept of personal identity. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 58, pp.581-594.
@

Rigterink, R. J.

(1991): What are beliefs (if they are anything at all)?. In: 'Metaphilosophy', vol. 22, pp.101-14.
@

Ringle, M.

(1979): Philosophical Perspectives in Artificial Intelligence. Humanities Press.
@

Ripley, C.

(1969): The identity theory and scientific hypotheses. In: ' Dialogue', vol. 2, pp.308-10.
@

Ripley, C.

(1984): Sperry's concept of consciousness. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 27, pp.399-423.
@

Rips, L. J.

(1995): The current status of research on concept combination. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 10, pp.72-104.
@

Ristau, C. A.

(1991): Cognitive Ethology: The Minds of Other Animals. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Robb, D.

(1997): The properties of mental causation. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 187, pp.178-94.
@

Robb, D.

(2001): Reply to Noordhof on mental causation. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 51, pp.90-94.
@

Robert, M.

(1983): Lewis's theory of personal identity. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 61, pp.58-67.
@

Roberts, L.

(1990): Searle's extension of the Chinese Room to connectionist machines . In: 'Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 2, pp.185-7.
@

Roberts, R. C.

(1995): Feeling one's emotions and knowing oneself. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 77, pp.319-38.
@

Roberts, R. C.

(1996): Propositions and animal emotion. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 71, pp.147-56.
@

Robinson, D.

(1991): On Crane and Mellor's argument against physicalism. In: 'Mind', vol. 100, pp.135-36.
@

Robinson, D. N.

(1976): What sort of persons are hemispheres? Another look at "split-brain" man. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 27, pp.73-8.
@

Robinson, H.

(1982): Behaviorism and stimulus materialism. In: ' Matter and Sense: A Critique of Contemporary Materialism'.
@

Robinson, H.

(1982): The disappearance theory. In: ' Matter and Sense: A Critique of Contemporary Materialism'.
@

Robinson, H.

(1993): Objections to Physicalism. Oxford University Press.
@

Robinson, H.

(2001): Davidson and nonreductive materialism: A tale of two cultures. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Robinson, H.

(2001): Davidson and nonreductive materialism: A tale of two cultures. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Robinson, H.

(2002): Dualism. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Robinson, J.

(1988): Personal identity and survival. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 85, pp.319-28.
@

Robinson, J.

(2004): Emotion: Biological fact or social construction. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1979): Do pains make a difference to our behavior?. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 16, pp.327-34.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1985): Toward eliminating Churchland's eliminationism. In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 13, pp.60-67.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1990): States and beliefs. In: 'Mind ', vol. 99, pp.33-51.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1991): Rationalism, expertise, and the Dreyfuses' critique of AI research . In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 29, pp.271-90.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1992): Penrose and mathematical ability. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 52, pp.80-88.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1992): Computers, Minds, and Robots. Temple University Press.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1995): Brain symbols and computationalist explanation. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 5, pp.25-44.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1995): Direct representation. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 80, pp.305-22.
@

Robinson, W. S.

(1996): Mild realism, causation, and folk psychology. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 8, pp.167-87.
@

Rockwell, T.

(2005): Attractor spaces as modules: A semi-eliminative reduction of symbolic AI to dynamic systems theory. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 15, pp.23-55.
@

Rockwell, W. T.

(1994): On what the mind is identical with. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.307-23.
@

Roessler, J.

(2005): Joint attention and the problem of other minds. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler, eds) Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds . In: '2005'.
@

Rogler, E.

(2000): On David Lewis' philosophy of mind. In: 'Protosociology ', vol. 14, pp.285-311.
@

Rohrlich, F.

(1997): Cognitive emergence. In: ' Philosophy of Science Supplement', vol. 64, pp.346-58.
@

Rollins, M.

(1989): Mental Imagery: On the Limits of Cognitive Science. Yale University Press.
@

Rollins, M.

(1994): Deep plasticity: The encoding approach to perceptual change. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 61, pp.39-54.
@

Rolls, E.

(2004): What are emotions, why do we have emotions, and what is their computational basis in the brain?. In: J. Fellous (Ed.): 'Who Needs Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Ronald, E.; Sipper, M.

(2001): Intelligence is not enough: On the socialization of talking machines. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 11, pp.567-576.
@

Rooijen, van, K.

(1987): Interactionism and evolution: A critique of Popper. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 38, pp.87-92.
@

Rorty, A.

(1976): The Identities of Persons. University of California Press.
@

Rorty, A. O.

(1976): A literary postscript: Characters, persons, selves, individuals . In: A. Rorty (Ed.): 'The Identities of Persons'. University of California Press.
@

Rorty, A. O.

(1978): Explaining emotions. In: '1978'.
@

Rorty, A. O.

(1980): Explaining Emotions. University of California Press.
@

Rorty, A. O.

(2004): Enough already with "theories of the emotions". In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Rorty, A. O; McLaughlin, B.

(1989): Perspectives on Self-Deception. University of California Press.
@

Rorty, R.

(1965): Mind-body identity, privacy, and categories. In: ' Review of Metaphysics', vol. 19, pp.24-54.
@

Rorty, R.

(1970): Incorrigibility as the mark of the mental. In: '1970'.
@

Rorty, R.

(1970): In defense of eliminative materialism. In: ' Review of Metaphysics', vol. 24, pp.112-21.
@

Rorty, R.

(1972): Functionalism, machines and incorrigibility. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 69, pp.203-20.
@

Rorty, R.

(1982): Contemporary philosophy of mind. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 53, pp.323-48.
@

Rorty, R.

(1993): Consciousness, intentionality, and pragmatism. In: S. Christensen; D. Turner (Ed.): 'Folk Psychology and the Philosophy of Mind'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Rosen, D. A.

(1975): An argument for the logical notion of a memory trace. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 42, pp.1-10.
@

Rosen, G.

(2001): Brandom on modality, normativity, and intentionality. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 63, pp.611-23.
@

Rosenbaum, S.

(1977): The property objection and the principles of identity. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 32.
@

Rosenberg, A.

(1985): Davidson's unintended attack on psychology. In: B. McLaughlin; E. LePore (Ed.): 'Action and Events'. Blackwell.
@

Rosenberg, A.

(1991): How is eliminative materialism possible?. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Mind and Common Sense'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Rosenberg, A.

(1999): Naturalistic epistemology for eliminative materialists. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 59, pp.335-358.
@

Rosenberg, J.

(1982): Conversation and intelligence. In: B. de Gelder (Ed.): ' Knowledge and Representation'. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
@

Rosenberg, J.

(1989): Connectionism and cognition. In: '1989'.
@

Rosenberg, J.

(1990): Treating connectionism properly: Reflections on Smolensky. In: 'Psychological Research', vol. 52.
@

Rosenschein, S. J.; Kaelbling, L. P.

(1995): A situated view of representation and control . In: 'Artificial Intelligence', vol. 73, pp.149-73.
@

Rosenthal, D. M.

(1980): Keeoing matter in mind. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.295-322.
@

Rosenthal, D. M.

(1983): Emotions and the self. In: K. Irani; G. Myers (Ed.): ' Emotion: Philosophical Studies'. Haven.
@

Rosenthal, D. M.

(2000): Introspection and self-interpretation. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 28, pp.201-33.
@

Ross, D.; Spurrett, D.

(2004): What to say to a skeptical metaphysician? A defense manual for cognitive and behavioral scientists. In: 'Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 27.
@

Ross, D.; Zawidzki, T.

(1994): Information and teleosemantics. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 32, pp.393-419.
@

Ross, J.

(1990): Against postulating central systems in the mind. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 57, pp.297-312.
@

Ross, P.

(2000): The relativity of color. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 123, pp.105-130.
@

Ross, P. A.

(1999): The limits of physicalism. Philosophy of Science 66:94-116. Schwartz, J. 1992. Who's afraid of multiple realizability?: Functionalism, reductionism, and connectionism . In: J. Dinsmore (Ed.): 'The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Ross, P. W.

(1999): The appearance and nature of color. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 37, pp.227-252.
@

Ross, P. W.

(2002): Explaining motivated desires. In: 'Topoi ', vol. 21, pp.199-207.
@

Rountree, J.

(1997): The plausibility of teleological content ascriptions: A reply to Pietroski. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 78, pp.404-20.
@

Routley, R.

(1982): Alleged problems in attributing beliefs, and intentionality, to animals . In: 'Inquiry', vol. 24, pp.385-417.
@

Routley, R.; MaCrae, V.

(1966): On the identity of sensations and physiological occurrences . In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 3.
@

Rovane, C.

(1987): The epistemology of first-person reference. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 84, pp.147-67.
@

Rovane, C.

(1990): Branching self-consciousness. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 99, pp.355-95.
@

Rowe, W.

(1987): Two concepts of freedom. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 61, pp.43-64.
@

Rowlands, M.

(1990): Anomalism, supervenience, and Davidson on content-individuation . In: 'Philosophia', vol. 295.
@

Rowlands, M.

(1991): A defense of behaviorism. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 19, pp.93-100.
@

Rowlands, M.

(1994): Connectionism and the language of thought. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 45, pp.485-503.
@

Rowlands, M.

(1995): Against methodological solipsism: The ecological Approach. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 8, pp.5-24.
@

Rowlands, M.

(1995): Externalism and token-token identity. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 24, pp.359-75.
@

Rowlands, M.

(1995): Supervenience and Materialism. Avebury.
@

Rowlands, M.

(1996): Teleological semantics. In: 'Mind ', vol. 106, pp.279-304.
@

Rowlands, M.

(1999): The Body in Mind: Understanding Cognitive Processes. Cambridge University Press.
@

Rozemond, M.

(2002): Descartes's Dualism. Harvard University Press.
@

Rudd, A.

(1997): Two types of externalism. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 47, pp.501-7.
@

Rudebusch, G.

(1986): Hoffman on Kripke's Wittgenstein. In: ' Philosophical Research Archives', vol. 12, pp.177-182.
@

Rueger, A.

(2000): Robust supervenience and emergence. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 67, pp.466-491.
@

Rueger, A.

(2001): Physical emergence, diachronic and synchronic. In: ' Synthese', vol. 124, pp.297-322.
@

Rueger, A.

(2004): Reduction, autonomy, and causal exclusion among physical properties . In: 'Synthese', vol. 139, pp.1-21.
@

Ruffman, T.

(1996): Do children understand the mind by means of a simulation or a theory? Evidence from their understanding of inference . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 11, pp.388-414.
@

Rundle, B.

(1986): Memory and causation. In: 'Philosophical Investigations ', vol. 9, pp.302-7.
@

Rupert, R.

(1998): On the relationship between naturalistic semantics and individuation criteria for terms in a language of thought . In: 'Synthese', vol. 117, pp.95-131.
@

Rupert, R.

(2000): Dispositions indisposed: Semantic atomism and Fodor's theory of content . In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 81, pp.325-349.
@

Rupert, R.

(2004): Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 101, pp.389-428.
@

Rupert, R. D.

(1999): Mental representations and Millikan's theory of intentionalcontent: Does biology chase causality?. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 37, pp.113-140.
@

Russell, B.

(1948): Analogy. In: 'Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits '.
@

Russell, E. S.

(1926): The notion of emergence. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 6, pp.39-48.
@

Russell, J. M.

(1984): Desires don't cause actions. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 84, pp.1-10.
@

Russell, P.

(2002): Pessimists, Pollyannas, and the new compatibilism. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Russell, S.

(1991): Inductive learning by machines. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 64, pp.37-64.
@

Russow, L-M.

(1984): Unlocking the Chinese Room. In: 'Nature and System ', vol. 6, pp.221-8.
@

Russow, L.

(1985): Dennett, mental images and images in context. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 45, pp.581-94.
@

Russow, L. M.

(1993): Fodor, Adams, and causal properties. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 6, pp.57-61.
@

Rust, J.

(1990): Delusions, irrationality, and cognitive science. In: '1990 '.
@

Rychlak, J. F.

(1976): Can psychology be objective about free will? Philosophical Psychologist 10:2-9. In: ' Revised version in New Ideas in Psychology', vol. 1, pp.213-29.
@

Rychlak, J. F.

(1991): Artificial Intelligence and Human Reason: A Teleological Critique . Columbia University Press.
@

Rychlak, J. F.

(1994): Four kinds of determinism and "free will": A response to Viney and Crosby. In: 'New Ideas in Psychology ', vol. 12, pp.143-46.
@

Rychlak, J. F.

(1994): Is free will a process or a content: Both? neither? Are we free to take a position on this question?. In: 'Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.62-72.
@

Rychlak, J. F.

(1996): Memory: A logical learning account. In: ' Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 17, pp.229-50.
@

Ryder, D.

(2004): SINBAD neurosemantics: A theory of mental representation. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.211-240.
@

Ryle, G.

(1949): The Concept of Mind. Hutchinson and Co.
@

Ryle, G.

(1979): On Thinking. Blackwell.

S


@

Sabates, M. H.

(2001): Varieties of exclusion. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 16, pp.13-42.
@

Sagal, P.; Borg, G.

(1993): The range principle and the problem of other minds. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 44, pp.477-91.
@

Sagawa, Y.; Sawai, H.; Sakai, N.

(2002): A hypothesis concerning a relationship between pleasantness and unpleasantness. In: K. Yasue; M. Jibu; T. Senta (Ed.): 'No Matter, Never Mind'. John Benjamins.
@

Saidel, E.

(1992): What price neurophilosophy?. In: ' Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 1, pp.461-68.
@

Saidel, E.

(1994): Content and causal powers. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 61, pp.658-65.
@

Saidel, E.

(1998): Beliefs, desires, and the ability to learn. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 35, pp.21-37.
@

Salmela, M.

(2002): Intentionality and feeling. A Sketch for a two-level account of emotional affectivity. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 3.
@

Samet, J.

(1986): Troubles with Fodor's nativism. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 10, pp.575-594.
@

Samet, J.; Flanagan, O. J.

(1989): Innate representations. In: S. Silvers (Ed.): 'Rerepresentation'. Kluwer.
@

Sampson, G.

(1973): In defence of Turing. In: 'Mind ', vol. 82, pp.592-94.
@

Sampson, G.

(1978): Linguistic universals as evidence for empiricism. In: ' 1978'.
@

Samuels, R.

(1998): What brains won't tell us about the mind: A critique of the neurobiological argument against representational nativism . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.548-570.
@

Samuels, R.

(2002): Nativism in cognitive science. Mind and Language 17:233-65. Samuels, R. 2004. Innateness in cognitive science. In: 'Trends in Cognitive Science', vol. 8, pp.136-141.
@

Sanders, J. T.

(1985): Experience, memory, and intelligence. In: 'Monist ', vol. 68, pp.507-21.
@

Sappington, A. A.

(1990): Recent psychological approaches to the free will versus determinism controversy. In: ' Psychological Bulletin', vol. 108, pp.19-29.
@

Sarkar, S.

(1992): Models of reduction and categories of reductionism. In: ' Synthese', vol. 91, pp.167-94.
@

Sarnecki, J.

(2004): The multimedia mnd: An analysis of Prinz on concepts. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 17, pp.403-18.
@

Sartorelli, J.

(1991): McGinn on content scepticism and Kripke's sceptical argument. In: 'Analysis', vol. 51, pp.79-84.
@

Sass, L.

(2004): Affectivity in schizophrenia: A phenomenological view. In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 11.
@

Sato, Y.; Ikegami, T.

(2004): Undecidability in the imitation game. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 14, pp.133-43.
@

Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S.; Rumbaugh, D. M.; Boysen, S.

(1980): Do apes use language?. In: 'American Scientist', vol. 68, pp.49-61.
@

Savage-Rumbaugh, S.; Brakke, K. E.

(1996): Animal language: Methodological and interpretative issues. In: C. Allen; D. Jamison (Ed.): ' Readings in Animal Cognition'. MIT Press.
@

Savitt, S.

(1974): Rorty's disappearance theory. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 28, pp.433-36.
@

Savitt, S.

(1987): Absolute informational content. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 70, pp.185-90.
@

Sawyer, S.

(1998): Privileged access to the world. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 76, pp.523-533.
@

Sawyer, S.

(1999): Am externalist account of introspectve knowledge. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 4, pp.358-78.
@

Sawyer, S.

(2002): In defense of Burge's thesis. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 107, pp.109-28.
@

Sawyer, S.

(2003): Sufficient absences. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 63, pp.202-8.
@

Sawyer, S.

(2004): Absences, presences, and sufficient conditions. In: ' Analysis', vol. 64, pp.354-57.
@

Saxe, R.

(2005): Against simulation: The argument from error. In: ' Trends in Cognitive Sciences', vol. 9, no.4, pp.174-79.
@

Saygin, A. P.; Cicekli, I.; Akman V.

(2000): Turing test: 50 years later. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 10, pp.463-518.
@

Sayre, K. M.

(1986): Intentionality and information processing: An alternative model for cognitive science. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 9, pp.121-38.
@

Sayre, K. M.

(1987): Cognitive science and the problem of semantic content. In: 'Synthese', vol. 70, pp.247-69.
@

Sayward, C.

(1995): Taking actions seriously. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp.51-60.
@

Schechtman, M.

(1990): Personhood and personal identity. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 87, pp.71-92.
@

Schechtman, M.

(2004): Personality and persistence: The many faces of personal survival . In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 41, pp.87-106.
@

Schectman, M.

(1994): The truth about memory. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 7, pp.3-18.
@

Schectman, M.

(1997): The brain/body problem. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 10, pp.149-64.
@

Scheerer, E.

(1994): Psychoneural isomorphism: Historical background and current relevance . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.183-210.
@

Scheffler, I.

(1950): The new dualism: Psychological and physical terms. In: '1950'.
@

Scher, S. J.; Rauscher, F.

(2002): Evolutionary Psychology: Alternative Perspectives . Kluwer.
@

Scheutz, M.

(1999): When physical systems realize functions. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 9, pp.161-196.
@

Scheutz, M.

(2002): Computationalism: New Directions. MIT Press. Scheutz, M. 2002. Computationalism: The next generation. In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): 'Computationalism: New Directions'. MIT Press.
@

Schiaffonati, V.

(2003): A framework for the foundation of the philosophy of artificial intelligence. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 13, pp.537-552.
@

Schiffer, S.

(1981): Truth and the theory of content. In: H. Parret (Ed.): ' Meaning and Understanding'. Berlin.
@

Schiffer, S.

(1986): Functionalism and belief. In: M. Brand; R. Harnish (Ed.): ' The Representation of Knowledge and Belief'. University of Arizona Press.
@

Schiffer, S.

(1987): Remnants of Meaning. MIT Press.
@

Schiffer, S.

(1989): Fodor's character. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): ' Information, Semantics, and Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Schiffer, S.

(1991): Does Mentalese have a compositional semantics?. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Schiffer, S.

(1991): Ceteris paribus laws. In: 'Mind ', vol. 100, pp.1-17.
@

Schiffer, S.

(1992): Boghossian on externalism and inference. In: ' Philosophical Issues', vol. 2, pp.29-38.
@

Schiffer, S.

(1994): The language-of-thought relation and its implications. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 76, pp.263-85.
@

Schiffer, S.

(2003): Two-dimensional semantics and propositional attitude content. In: 'The Things We Mean'.
@

Schlagel, R.

(1999): Why not artificial consciousness or thought?. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 9, pp.3-28.
@

Schlagel, R. H.

(1977): The mind-body identity impasse. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 14, pp.231-37.
@

Scholl, B. J.

(1997): Reasoning, rationality, and architectural resolution. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 10, pp.451-470.
@

Scholl, B. J.; Leslie, A. M.

(1999): Modularity, development and "theory of mind. In: '" Mind and Language', vol. 14, pp.131-153.
@

Schonbein, W.

(2005): Cognition and the power of continuous dynamical systems. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 15, pp.57-71.
@

Schopman, J.; Shawky, A.

(1996): Remarks on the impact of connectionism on our thinking about concepts. In: P. Millican; A. Clark (Ed.): ' Machines and Thought'. Oxford University Press.
@

Schouten, M. K. D.; de Jong, H. L.

(1998): Defusing eliminative materialism: Reference and revision. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp.489-509.
@

Schroder, J.

(1998): Emergence: Non-deducibility or downwards causation?. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 48, pp.433-52.
@

Schroder, J.

(1998): Knowledge of rules, causal systematicity, and the language of thought . In: 'Synthese', vol. 117, pp.313-330.
@

Schroder, J.

(2002): The supervenience argument and the generalization problem. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 56, pp.319-28.
@

Schroeder, S.

(1997): The concept of dreaming: On three theses by Malcolm. In: 'Philosophical Investigations', vol. 20, pp.15-38.
@

Schroeder, T.

(2003): Donald Davidson's theory of mind is non-normative. In: 'Philosopher's Imprint', vol. 3, pp.1-14.
@

Schroeder, T.

(2004): Three Faces of Desire. Oxford University Press.
@

Schroeder, T.

(2004): New norms for teleosemantics. In: H. Clapin (Ed.): ' Representation in Mind'. Elsevier.
@

Schroeter, L.

(2003): Gruesome diagonals. In: 'Philosophers' Imprint ', vol. 3, no.3.
@

Schroeter, L.

(2004): The rationalist foundations of Chalmers' two-dimensional semantics . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 18, pp.227-55.
@

Schueler, G. F.

(1991): Pro-attitudes and direction of fit. In: 'Mind ', vol. 100, pp.277-81.
@

Schueler, G. F.

(1995): Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action . MIT Press.
@

Schurz, G.

(2002): McCall and Raatikainen on mechanism and incompleteness. In: 'Facta Philosophica', vol. 4, pp.171-74.
@

Schutter, D.; van Honk, J.; Panksepp, J.

(2004): Introducing transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) and its property of causal inference in investigating brain-function relationships . In: 'Synthese', vol. 141, pp.155-73.
@

Schwartz, G.

(1996): Symbols and thought. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 106, pp.399-407.
@

Schwartz, J.

(1991): Reduction, elimination, and the mental. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 58, pp.203-20.
@

Schwartz, J.

(1992): Propositional attitude psychology as an ideal type. In: 'Topoi', vol. 11, pp.5-26.
@

Schwartz, R.

(1980): Imagery: There is more to it than meets the eye. In: ' Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 1980.
@

Schwartz, R.

(1995): Is mathematical competence innate?. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 62, pp.227-40.
@

Schweizer, P.

(1998): The truly total Turing Test. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 8, pp.263-272.
@

Schweizer, P.

(2001): Realization, reduction and psychological autonomy. In: 'Synthese', vol. 126, pp.383-405.
@

Schwitzgebel, E.

(1996): Theories in children and the rest of us. In: ' Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 3.
@

Schwitzgebel, E.

(1999): Representation and desire: A philosophical error with consequences for theory-of-mind research. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 12, pp.157-180.
@

Schwitzgebel, E.

(2001): In-between believing. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 51.
@

Schwitzgebel, E.

(2002): A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. In: 'Nous', vol. 36, pp.249-75.
@

Scott, A.

(2004): Reductionism revisited. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 11, no.2, pp.51-68.
@

Scott-Kakures, D.

(1996): Self-deception and internal irrationality. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.31-56.
@

Scriven, M.

(1953): The mechanical concept of mind. In: '1953'.
@

Scriven, M.

(1956): A study of radical behaviorism. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 1, pp.88-130.
@

Scriven, M.

(1960): The compleat robot: A prolegomena to androidology. In: S. Hook (Ed.): 'Dimensions of Mind'. New York University Press.
@

Scriven, M.

(1966): The limitations of the identity theory. In: P. Feyerabend; G. Maxwell (Ed.): ' Mind, Matter, and Method: Essays in Philosophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl'. University of Minnesota Press.
@

Scruton, R.

(1984): Critical Notice: Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. In: 'Mind', vol. 93, pp.592-602.
@

Seager, W.

(2000): Real patterns and surface metaphysics. In: A. Brook; D. Ross; D. Thompson (Ed.): 'Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment'. MIT Press.
@

Seager, W.

(2000): Introspection and the elementary acts of mind. In: ' Dialogue', vol. 39, pp.53-76.
@

Seager, W.

(2001): The constructed and the secret self. In: A. Brook; R. DeVidi (Ed.): 'Self-Reference and Self-Awareness'. John Benjamins.
@

Seager, W.

(2001): The constructed and the secret self. In: A. Brook; R. DeVidi (Ed.): 'Self-reference and Self-Awareness'. John Benjamins.
@

Seager, W.

(2002): Emotional introspection. In: 'Consciousness and Cognition ', vol. 11, pp.666-687.
@

Seager, W. E.

(1981): The anomalousness of the mental. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.389-401.
@

Seager, W. E.

(1988): Weak supervenience and materialism. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 48, pp.697-709.
@

Seager, W. E.

(1991): Disjunctive laws and supervenience. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 51, pp.93-98.
@

Seager, W. E.

(1992): Thought and syntax. In: ' Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 1992.
@

Seager, W. E.

(1992): Externalism and token identity. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 42, pp.439-48.
@

Seager, W. E.

(1993): Fodor's theory of content: problems and objections. In: 'Phiosophy of Science', vol. 60, pp.262-77.
@

Searle, J.

(1984): Indeterminacy, empiricism, and the first person. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 84.
@

Searle, J.

(2000): Consciousness, free action and the brain. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 7, pp.3-22.
@

Searle, J.

(2002): Skepticism about rules and intentionalilty. In: ' Consciousness and Language'.
@

Searle, J.

(2003): Rationality in Action. MIT Press.
@

Searle, J.

(2004): Mind: A Brief Introduction. Oxford University Press.
@

Searle, J. R.

(1980): Minds, brains and programs. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 3, pp.417-57.
@

Searle, J. R.

(1983): Intentionality. Cambridge University Press.
@

Searle, J. R.

(1984): Intentionality and its place in nature. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 61, pp.3-16.
@

Searle, J. R.

(1984): Minds, Brains and Science. Harvard University Press.
@

Searle, J. R.

(1987): Minds and brains without programs. In: C. Blakemore (Ed.): 'Mindwaves'. Blackwell.
@

Searle, J. R.

(1989): Reply to Jacquette. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 49, pp.701-8.
@

Searle, J. R.

(1990): Is the brain's mind a computer program?. In: ' Scientific American', vol. 262, no.1, pp.26-31.
@

Searle, J. R.

(1990): Is the brain a digital computer?. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 64, pp.21-37.
@

Searle, J. R.

(2001): Free will as a problem in neurobiology. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 76, pp.491-514.
@

Searle, J. R.

(2002): Twenty-one years in the Chinese room. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Sebeok, T. A.; Umiker-Sebeok, J.

(1980): Speaking of Apes: A Critical Anthology of Two-Way Communication with Man. Plenum Press.
@

Sedivy, S.

(2004): Minds: Contents without vehicles. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 17, pp.149-181.
@

Segal, G.

(1989): The return of the individual. In: 'Mind ', vol. 98, pp.39-57.
@

Segal, G.

(1989): Seeing what is not there. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 97, pp.189-214.
@

Segal, G.

(1991): Defence of a reasonable individualism. In: 'Mind ', vol. 100, pp.485-94.
@

Segal, G.

(2000): A Slim Book about Narrow Content. MIT Press.
@

Segal, G.; Sober, E.

(1991): The causal efficacy of content. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 63, pp.1-30.
@

Sehon S. R.

(1997): Natural kind terms and the status of folk psychology. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 34, pp.333-44.
@

Sehon, S.

(1998): Connectionism and the causal theory of action explanation. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 11, pp.511-532.
@

Sehon, S. R.

(1994): Teleology and the nature of mental states. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 31, pp.63-72.
@

Seibt, J.

(2002): Fission, sameness, and survival: Parfit's branch line argument revisited . In: 'Metaphysica', vol. 1, no.2, pp.95-134.
@

Seidel, A.

(1988): Searle on the biological basis of cognition. In: ' Analysis', vol. 48, pp.26-28.
@

Seidel, A.

(1989): Chinese Rooms A, B and C. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 20, pp.167-73.
@

Seligman, M.; Yellen, A.

(1987): What is a dream?. In: ' Behavior Research and Therapy', vol. 25, pp.1-24.
@

Sellars, W.

(1948): Concepts as involving laws and inconceivable without them. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 15, pp.287-313.
@

Sellars, W.

(1952): Mind, meaning, and behavior. In: '1952'.
@

Sellars, W.

(1954): A note on Popper's argument for dualism. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 15, pp.23-24.
@

Sellars, W.

(1956): Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 1, pp.253-329.
@

Sellars, W.

(1956): Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 1, pp.253-329.
@

Sellars, W.

(1965): The identity approach to the mind-body problem. In: ' Review of Metaphysics', vol. 18, pp.430-51.
@

Sellars, W.

(1974): Conceptual change. In: ' Essays in Philosophy and its History'.
@

Sellars, W.; Chisholm, R.

(1957): Intentionality and the mental: A correspondence. In: 'Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 2, pp.507-39.
@

Senor, T. D.

(1992): Two-factor theories, meaning holism, and intentionalistic psychology: A reply to Fodor. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 5, pp.133-51.
@

Settle, T.

(1993): How determinism refutes compatibilism. In: ' Religious Studies', vol. 29, pp.353-62.
@

Seymour, D.

(1993): Some of the difference in the world: Crane on intentional causation . In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 43, pp.83-89.
@

Shaffer, J.

(1961): Could mental states be brain processes?. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 58, pp.813-22.
@

Shaffer, J.

(1963): Mental events and the brain. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 60, pp.160-6.
@

Shaffer, J.

(1977): Personal identity: The implications of brain bisection and brain transplants. In: ' Journal of Medicine and Philosophy', vol. 2, pp.147-61.
@

Shaffer, J. A.

(1964): Philosophy of Mind. Prentice-Hall.
@

Shagrir, O.

(1997): Two dogmas of computationalism. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 7, pp.321-44.
@

Shagrir, O.

(1998): Multiple realization, computation and the taxonomy of psychological states. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 114, pp.445-461.
@

Shagrir, O.

(1999): More on global supervenience. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 59, pp.691-701.
@

Shagrir, O.

(2001): Content, computation and externalism. In: 'Mind ', vol. 110, pp.369-400.
@

Shagrir, O.

(2002): Global supervenience, coincident entities, and anti-individualism . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 109, pp.171-96.
@

Shalom, A.

(1985): The Body-Mind Conceptual Framework and the Problem of Personal Identity . Humanities Press.
@

Shanker, S.

(1984): Sceptical confusions about rule-following. In: 'Mind ', vol. 93, pp.423-29.
@

Shanon, B.

(1983): Descartes' puzzle -- An organismic approach. In: ' Cognition and Brain Theory', vol. 6, pp.185-95.
@

Shanon, B.

(1988): Remarks on the modularity of mind. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 39, pp.331-52.
@

Shanon, B.

(1989): A simple comment regarding the Turing test. In: ' Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior', vol. 19, pp.249-56.
@

Shanon, B.

(1991): Representations -- senses and reasons. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.355-74.
@

Shanon, B.

(1992): Are connectionist models cognitive?. In: '1992'.
@

Shanon, B.

(1993): The Representational and the Presentational: An Essay on Cognition and the Study of Mind. Prentice-Hall.
@

Shapiro, L.

(1992): Darwin and disjunction: Foraging theory and univocal assignments of content. In: ' Philosophy of Science Association', vol. 1992.
@

Shapiro, L.

(1996): Representation from bottom to top. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 26, pp.523-42.
@

Shapiro, L.

(2000): Multiple realizations. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 97, pp.635-654.
@

Shapiro, L.

(2001): Mind the adaptation. In: D. Walsh (Ed.): ' Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Shapiro, L.

(2004): Brandom on the normativity of meaning. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 68, pp.141-60.
@

Shapiro, L.

(2004): The Mind Incarnate. MIT Press.
@

Shapiro, L. A.

(1993): Content, kinds, and individualism in Marr's theory of vision. In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 102, pp.489-513.
@

Shapiro, L. A.

(1997): A clearer vision. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 64, pp.131-53.
@

Shapiro, L. A.

(1997): Junk representations. In: '1997'.
@

Shapiro, L. A.

(1997): The nature of nature: Rethinking naturalistic theories of intentionality. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 10, pp.309-322.
@

Shapiro, L.; Epstein, W.

(1998): Evolutionary theory meets cognitive psychology: A more selective perspective. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp.171-94.
@

Shapiro, S. C.

(1995): Computationalism. In: 'Minds and Machines ', vol. 5, pp.467-87.
@

Sharpe, R.

(1987): The very idea of a folk psychology. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 30, pp.381-93.
@

Sharpe, R.

(1989): Dennett's journey towards panpsychism. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 32, pp.233-40.
@

Sharpe, R. A.

(1997): One cheer for the simulation theory. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 40, pp.115-31.
@

Sharvy, R.

(1985): Searle on programs and intentionality. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 11, pp.39-54.
@

Shatz, D.

(1985): Free will and the structure of motivation. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 10, pp.451-82.
@

Shea, N.

(2003): Does externalism entail the anomalism of the mental?. In: ' The Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 53, pp.201-213.
@

Sheldon, W. H.

(1946): Are naturalists materialists?. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 43, pp.197-209.
@

Shepard, R.; Cooper, L.

(1982): Mental Images and their Transformations. MIT Press.
@

Sher, G.

(1975): Sentences in the brain. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 36, pp.94-99.
@

Shieber, S.

(2004): The Turing Test: Verbal Behavior as the Hallmark of Intelligence . MIT Press.
@

Shieber, S. M.

(1994): Lessons from a restricted Turing test. In: ' Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery', vol. 37, pp.70-82.
@

Shier, D.

(1997): How can pictures be propositions?. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 10, pp.65-75.
@

Shirley, E. S.

(1974): Rorty's "disappearance" version of the identity theory. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 25, pp.73-75.
@

Shoemaker, D. W.

(1999): Selves and moral units. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 80, pp.391-419.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1959): Personal identity and memory. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 56, pp.868-902.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1963): Self-Knowledge and Self-Identity. Cornell University Press.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1965): Ziff's other minds. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 62, pp.587-89.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1970): Persons and their pasts. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 7, pp.269-85.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1981): Some varieties of functionalism. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 12, pp.93-119.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1988): On knowing one's own mind. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 2, pp.183-209.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1990): First-person access. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 4, pp.187-214.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1994): Self-knowledge and "inner sense". In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 54, pp.249-314.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1995): Moore's paradox and self-knowledge. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 77, pp.211-28.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(1999): Self, body, and coincidence. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 73, pp.287-306.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(2001): Realization and mental causation. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(2002): Kim on emergence. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 58, pp.53-63.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(2003): Moran on self-knowledge. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 3, pp.391-401.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(2003): Realization, micro-realization, and coincidence. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 67, pp.1-23.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(2003): Self, body, and coincidence. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 63, pp.287-306.
@

Shoemaker, S.

(2004): Identity, Cause, and Mind: Philosophical Essays. Oxford University Press.
@

Shoemaker, S.; Swinburne, S.

(1984): Personal Identity: Great Debates in Philosophy. Blackwell.
@

Shogenji, T.

(1992): Boomerang defense of rule following. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 30, pp.115-122.
@

Shogenji, T.

(1993): Modest scepticism about rule-following. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 71, pp.486-500.
@

Shogenji, T.

(1995): The problem of rule-following in compositional semantics. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 33, pp.97-108.
@

Shope, R. K.

(1973): Functional equivalence and the defense of materialism. In: 'Philosophical Forum', vol. 4, pp.500-12.
@

Shope, R. K.

(1973): Remembering, knowledge, and memory traces. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 33, pp.303-22.
@

Shorter, J. M.

(1962): More about bodily continuity and personal identity. In: 'Analysis', vol. 22, pp.79-85.
@

Shuford, H.

(1966): Logical behaviorism and intentionality. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 32, pp.246-51.
@

Sidelle, A.

(1999): On the prospects for a theory of personal identity. In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 26, pp.351-72.
@

Sider, T.

(2003): Maximality and microphysical supervenience. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 66, pp.139-149.
@

Siderits, M.

(1987): Beyond compatibilism: A Buddhist approach to freedom and determinism . In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 24, pp.149-59.
@

Siderits, M.

(1988): Ehring on Parfit's relation R. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 48, pp.29-32.
@

Siegler, F. A.

(1967): Remembering dreams. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 17, pp.14-24.
@

Siewert, C.

(2003): Self-knowledge and rationality: Shoemaker on self-blindness. In: B. Gertler (Ed.): 'Privileged Access: Philosophical Accounts of Self-Knowledge'. Ashgate.
@

Sikora, R. I.

(1974): Rorty's mark of the mental and his disappearance theory. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 4, pp.191-93.
@

Sikora, R. I.

(1975): Rorty's new mark of the mental. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 35, pp.192-94.
@

Sikora, R. I.

(1977): The argument from analogy is not an argument for other mnds. In: 'American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 14, pp.137-41.
@

Silberstein, M.

(1998): Emergence and the mind-body problem. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 5, pp.464-82.
@

Silberstein, M.

(2001): Converging on emergence: Consciousness, causation and explanation . In: 'Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 8, pp.61-98.
@

Silberstein, M.; McGeever, J.

(1999): The search for ontological emergence. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.182-200.
@

Silverberg, A.

(1992): Putnam on functionalism. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 67, pp.111-31.
@

Silverberg, A.

(1994): Meaning holism and intentional content. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 75, pp.29-53.
@

Silverberg, A.

(1995): Narrow content: A defense. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 33, pp.109-27.
@

Silverberg, A.

(1996): Psychological laws and nonmonotonic logic. In: ' Erkenntnis', vol. 44, pp.199-224.
@

Silverberg, A.

(2003): Psychological laws. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 58, pp.275-302.
@

Silverman, H. J.

(2000): Philosophy and Desire. Routledge.
@

Silvers, S.

(1991): On naturalizing the semantics of mental representation. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 42, pp.49-73.
@

Silvers, S.

(1997): Nonreductive naturalism. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 12, pp.163-84.
@

Silvers, S.

(2003): Individualism, internalism, and wide supervenience. In: M. Frapolli; E. Romero (Ed.): 'Meaning, Basic Self-Knowledge, and Mind'. CSLI.
@

Simon, H.A.; Eisenstadt, S.A.

(2003): A Chinese room that understands. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Simon, M.A.

(1970): Materialism, mental language, and the mind-body identity. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 30, pp.514-32.
@

Simons, P.

(1995): Mind and opacity. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 49, pp.131-46.
@

Sinnott-Armstrong, W.

(2002): A light theory of color. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 110, pp.267-284.
@

Sizer, L.

(2000): Towards a computational theory of mood. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 51, pp.743-770.
@

Skarda, S.

(1986): Explaining behavior: Bringing the brain back in. In: ' Inquiry', vol. 29, pp.187-201.
@

Skillen, A.

(1984): Mind and matter: a problem which refuses dissolution. In: 'Mind', vol. 93, pp.514-26.
@

Skinner, B. F.

(1945): The operational analysis of psychological terms. In: 'Psychological Review', vol. 52, pp.270-78.
@

Skokowski, P.

(2004): Structural content: A naturalistic approach to implicit belief . In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 71, pp.362-369.
@

Skokowski, P. G.

(1994): Can computers carry content "inexplicitly"?. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.333-44.
@

Slater, C.

(1994): Discrimination without indication: Why Dretske can't lean on learning . In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.163-80.
@

Slezak, P.

(1982): Godel's theorem and the mind. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 33, pp.41-52.
@

Slezak, P.

(1983): Descartes's diagonal deduction. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 34, pp.13-36.
@

Slife, B. D.

(1994): Free will and time: That "stuck" feeling. In: ' Journal of Theoretical and Philsophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.1-12.
@

Sloane, E. H.

(1945): Reductionism. In: 'Psychological Review ', vol. 52, pp.214-23.
@

Sloman, A.

(1978): The Computer Revolution in Philosophy. Harvester.
@

Sloman, A.

(1986): Did Searle attack Strong Strong AI or Weak Strong AI?. In: Cohn; Thomas (Ed.): 'Artificial Intelligence and its Applications'. Chichester.
@

Sloman, A.

(1993): The mind as a control system. In: C. Hookway; D. Peterson (Ed.): 'Philosophy and Cognitive Science'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Sloman, A.

(2002): The irrelevance of Turing machines to artificial intelligence. In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): 'Computationalism: New Directions'. MIT Press.
@

Sloman, A.; Chrisley, R.

(2003): Virtual machines and consciousness. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 10.
@

Slors, M.

(1996): Why Dennett cannot explain what it is to adopt the intentional stance . In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 46, pp.93-98.
@

Slors, M.

(2001): Personal identity, memory, and circularity: An alternative for q-memory . In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 98, pp.186-214.
@

Slote, M.

(1966): Induction and other minds. In: 'Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 20, pp.341-60.
@

Slote, M.

(1980): Understanding free will. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp.136-51.
@

Slote, M.

(1982): Selective necessity and the free will problem. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 74, pp.5-24.
@

Slote, M. A.

(1969): Free will, determinism, and the theory of important criteria. In: 'Inquiry', vol. 12, pp.317-38.
@

Smart, B.

(1976): Synchronous and diachronous selves. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 6, pp.13-33.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1959): Ryle on mechanism and psychology. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 9, pp.349-55.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1959): Sensations and brain processes. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 68, pp.141-56.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1960): Sensations and brain processes: A rejoinder to Dr. Pitcher and Mr. Joske. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philsophy', vol. 38, pp.252-54.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1961): Further remarks on sensations and brain processes. In: '1961'.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1961): Godel's theorem, Church's theorem, and mechanism. In: 'Synthese', vol. 13, pp.105-10.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1962): Brain processes and incorrigibility. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 40, pp.68-70.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1962): Brain processes and incorrigibility. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 40, pp.68-70.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1963): Materialism. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 60, pp.651-62.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1963): Free will, praise and blame. In: 'Mind ', vol. 70, pp.291-306.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1965): The identity thesis: A reply to Professor Garrett. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 43, pp.82-3.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1972): Further thoughts on the identity theory. In: 'Monist ', vol. 56, pp.177-92.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1975): On some criticisms of a physicalist theory of colors. In: C. Cheng (Ed.): 'Philosophical Aspects of the Mind-Body Problem'. University Press of Hawaii.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1978): The content of physicalism. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 28, pp.339-41.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1981): Physicalism and emergence. In: 'Neuroscience ', vol. 6, pp.109-13.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1985): Davidson's minimal materialism. In: B. Vermazen; M. Hintikka (Ed.): 'Essays on Davidson'. Oxford University Press.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1992): Wittgenstein, following a rule, and scientific psychology. In: E. Ullmann-Margalit (Ed.): 'The Scientific Enterprise'. Kluwer.
@

Smart, J. J. C.

(1995): `Looks red' and dangerous talk. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 70.
@

Smilansky, S.

(1990): Is libertarian free will worth wanting?. In: ' Philosophical Investigations', vol. 13, pp.273-76.
@

Smilansky, S.

(1990): Van Inwagen on the "obviousness" of libertarian moral responsibility . In: 'Analysis', vol. 50, pp.29-33.
@

Smilansky, S.

(1993): Does the free will debate rest on a mistake?. In: ' Philosophical Papers', vol. 22, pp.173-88.
@

Smilansky, S.

(2000): Free Will and Illusion. Oxford University Press.
@

Smilansky, S.

(2001): Free will: From nature to illusion. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 101, pp.71-95.
@

Smilansky, S.

(2002): Free will, fundamental dualism,and the centrality of illusion. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Smilansky, S.

(2003): Free will and the mystery of modesty. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 40, pp.105-118.
@

Smilansky, S.

(2003): Compatibilism: The argument from shallowness. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 115, pp.257-82.
@

Smit, H.

(1995): Are animal displays bodily movements or manifestations of the mind? . In: 'Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.13-19.
@

Smith, A.

(1986): Brain-mind philosophy. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 29, pp.203-15.
@

Smith, A. D.

(1993): Non-reductive physicalism?. In: H. Robinson (Ed.): ' Objections to Physicalism'. Oxford University Press.
@

Smith, B.

(1987): The correspondence continuum. In: 'CSLI-', vol. 87.
@

Smith, B.

(1988): On the semantics of clocks. In: J. Fetzer (Ed.): ' Aspects of AI'. Kluwer.
@

Smith, B. C.

(1996): Does science underwrite our folk psychology?. In: W. O'Donahue; R. Kitchener (Ed.): 'The Philosophy of Psychology'. Sage Publications.
@

Smith, B. C.

(2002): The foundations of computing. In: M. Scheutz (Ed.): ' Computationalism: New Directions'. MIT Press.
@

Smith, D. C.

(2001): Meaning, normativity, and reductive naturalism. In: ' Sorites', vol. 12, pp.60-65.
@

Smith, D. C.

(2003): What is so magical about a theory of intrinsic intentionality?. In: 'Philosophical Papers', vol. 32, pp.83-96.
@

Smith, D. M.

(1994): Toward a perspicuous characterization of intentional states. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 74, pp.103-20.
@

Smith, E. E.; Medin, D. L.

(1981): Categories and Concepts. Harvard University Press.
@

Smith, M.

(1988): Reason and desire. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 88, pp.243-58.
@

Smith, M.

(1997): A theory of freedom and responsibility. In: G. Cullity; B. Gaut (Ed.): 'Ethics and Practical Reason'. Oxford University Press.
@

Smith, M. A.

(1993): Color, transparency, mind-independence. In: J. Haldane; C. Wright (Ed.): 'Reality, Representation, and Projection'. Oxford University Press.
@

Smith, N. ed.

(2002): Reading McDowell: On Mind and World. Routledge.
@

Smith, P.

(1982): Bad news for anomalous monism?. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 42, pp.220-4.
@

Smith, P.

(1987): Subjectivity and colour vision. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 61, pp.245-81.
@

Smith, P.; Jones, O.

(1986): The Philosophy of Mind: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press.
@

Smolensky, P.

(1987): The constituent structure of connectionist mental states. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 26, pp.137-60.
@

Smolensky, P.

(1987): Connectionist AI, symbolic AI, and the brain. In: ' AI Review', vol. 1, pp.95-109.
@

Smolensky, P.

(1988): On the proper treatment of connectionism. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 11, pp.1-23.
@

Smolensky, P.

(1990): Tensor product variable binding and the representation of symbolic structures in connectionist systems. In: 'Artificial Intelligence', vol. 46, pp.159-216.
@

Smolensky, P.

(1991): Connectionism, constituency and the language of thought. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Smolensky, P.

(1995): Constituent structure and explanation in an integrated connectionist/symbolic cognitive architecture. In: C. Macdonald (Ed.): 'Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation'. Blackwell.
@

Smolensky, P.

(1995): On the projectable predicates of connectionist psychology: A case for belief. In: C. Macdonald (Ed.): ' Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation'. Blackwell.
@

Smythe, T.

(1983): Our knowledge of other minds. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 13, pp.35-52.
@

Smythies, J. R.

(1994): Requiem for the identity theory. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 37, pp.311-29.
@

Snowdon, P. F.

(1989): On formulating materialism and dualism. In: J. Heil (Ed.): 'Cause, Mind, and Reality: Essays Honoring C. B. Martin'. Kluwer.
@

Soames, S.

(1998): Skepticism about meaning, indeterminacy, normativity, and the rule-following paradox. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supp.Vol ., vol. 23
@

Soames, S.

(1998): Facts, truth conditions, and the skeptical solution to the rule-following paradox. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 12, pp.313-48.
@

Sobel, D.; Copp, D.

(2001): Against direction of fit accounts of belief and desire. In: 'Analysis', vol. 61, pp.44-53.
@

Sobel, J. H.

(1998): Puzzles for the Will. University of Toronto Press.
@

Sober, E.

(1976): Mental representations. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 33, pp.101-48.
@

Sober, E.

(1978): Psychologism. In: ' Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior', vol. 8, pp.165-91.
@

Sober, E.

(1981): The evolution of rationality. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 46, pp.95-120.
@

Sober, E.

(1985): Panglossian functionalism and the philosophy of mind. In: 'Synthese', vol. 64, pp.165-93.
@

Sober, E.

(1990): Putting the function back into functionalism. In: W. Lycan (Ed.): 'Mind and Cognition'. Blackwell.
@

Sober, E.

(1999): Physicalism from a probabilistic point of view. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 95, pp.135-74.
@

Sober, E.

(2000): Evolution and the problem of other minds. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 97, pp.365-387.
@

Sober, E.

(2001): The principle of conservatism in cognitive ethology. In: D. Walsh (Ed.): 'Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Solomon, R. C.

(1973): Emotion and choice. In: 'Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 17, pp.20-41.
@

Solomon, R. C.

(1975): Minimal incorrigibility. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 53, pp.254-56.
@

Solomon, R. C.

(1984): The Passions: The Myth and Nature of Human Emotions. Doubleday.
@

Solomon, R. C.

(1999): The philosophy of emotions. In: M. Lewis; J. Haviland-Jones (Ed.): 'Handbook of Emotions'. Guilford Press.
@

Solomon, R. C.

(2003): Emotions, thoughts, and feelings: What is a "cognitive theory of the emotions and does it neglect affectivity?. In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Solomon, R. C.

(2004): Emotions, thoughts, and feelings: Emotions as ngagements with the world. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Solomon, R. C.

(2004): Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions . Oxford University Press.
@

Sorabji, R.

(1992): Animal minds. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 31, pp.1-18.
@

Sosa, E.

(1965): Professor Malcolm on "Scientific materialism and the identity theory" . In: 'Dialogue', vol. 4, pp.422-23.
@

Sosa, E.

(1965): Professor Malcolm on `Scientific materialism and the identity theory' . In: 'Dialogue', vol. 3, pp.422-23.
@

Sosa, E.

(1984): Mind-body interaction and supervenient causation. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 9, pp.271-81.
@

Sosa, E.

(1991): Between internalism and externalism. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): ' Consciousness'. Ridgeview.
@

Sosa, E.

(1993): Abilities, concepts, and externalism. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Sosa, E.

(1993): Abilities, concepts, and externalism. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): 'Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Sosa, E.

(1993): Davidson's thinking causes. In: J. Heil; A. Mele (Ed.): ' Mental Causation'. Oxford University Press.
@

Sosa, E.

(1999): The essentials of persons. In: 'Dialectica ', vol. 53, pp.227-41.
@

Sosa, E.

(2002): Privileged access. In: Q. Smith; A. Jokic (Ed.): ' Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives'. Oxford University Press.
@

Sosa, E.; Galloway, D.

(2001): Man the rational animal?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 122, pp.165-78.
@

Soteriou, M.

(2005): Mental action and the epistemology of mind. In: 'Nous ', vol. 39, pp.83-105.
@

Sousa, de, R.

(1979): The rationality of emotions. In: '1979'.
@

Sousa, de, R.

(1987): The Rationality of Emotion. MIT Press.
@

Sousa, de, R.

(2002): Emotional truth. In: 'Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 76, pp.247-63.
@

Sousa, de, R.

(2004): Emotions: What I know, what I'd like to think I know, and what I'd like to think. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): ' Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Spackman, J.

(2002): Color, relativism, and realism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 108, pp.251-88.
@

Spence, S. A.

(1996): Free will in the light of neuropsychiatry. In: ' Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology', vol. 3, pp.75-90.
@

Spencer, W.

(1930): Our Knowledge of Other Minds. Yale University Press.
@

Spencer-Smith, R.

(1995): Reductionism and emergent properties. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 95, pp.113-29.
@

Sperber, D.

(1996): Explaining Culture: A Naturalistic Approach. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
@

Sperber, D.

(1997): Intuitive and reflective beliefs. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp.67-83.
@

Sperry, R. W.

(1969): A modified concept of consciousness. In: ' Psychological Review', vol. 76, pp.532-36.
@

Sperry, R. W.

(1984): Consciousness, personal identity and the divided brain. In: 'Neuropsychologia', vol. 22, pp.611-73.
@

Sperry, R. W.

(1991): In defense of mentalism and emergent interaction. In: 'Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 12, pp.221-245.
@

Spicer, F.

(2004): On the identity of concepts, and the compatibility of externalism and privileged access. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 41, pp.155-168.
@

Spicer, F.

(2004): Emotional behaviour and the scope of belief-desire explanation. In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): 'Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality'. Oxford University Press.
@

Spilsbury, R. J.

(1952): Mentality in machines. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 26, pp.27-60.
@

Spohn, W.

(1997): The character of color predicates: A materialist view. In: M. Anduschus; A. Newen; W. Kunne (Ed.): 'Direct Reference, Indexicality, and Propositional Attitudes'. CSLI Press.
@

Sprague, E.

(1999): Persons and their Minds: A Philosophical Investigation. Westview Press.
@

Sprigge, T. L. S.

(1988): Personal and impersonal identity. In: 'Mind ', vol. 97, pp.29-49.
@

Sprigge, T. L. S.

(1992): Ayer on other minds. In: L. Hahn (Ed.): ' The Philosophy of A. J. Ayer'. Open Court.
@

Spurrett, D.

(2001): What physical properties are. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 82, pp.201-225.
@

Spurrett, D.; Papineau, D.

(1999): A note on the completeness of "physics". In: 'Analysis', vol. 59, pp.25-29.
@

Squires, R.

(1969): Memory unchained. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 78, pp.178-96.
@

Sripada, C. S.; Stich, S. P.

(2004): Evolution, culture, and the irrationality of the emotions. In: D. Evans; P. Cruse (Ed.): ' Emotion, Evolution, and Rationality'. Oxford University Press.
@

Stabler, E.

(1987): Kripke on functionalism and automata. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 70, pp.1-22.
@

Stace, W. T.

(1939): Novelty, indeterminism, and emergence. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 48, pp.296-310.
@

Stainton, R.

(1999): Robust belief states and the right/wrong distinction. In: 'Disputatio', vol. 6.
@

Stalker, D. F.

(1978): Why machines can't think: A reply to James Moor. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 34, pp.317-20.
@

Stalnaker, R.

(1991): How to do semantics for the language of thought. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Stalnaker, R.

(1993): Twin earth revisited. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 63, pp.297-311.
@

Stalnaker, R.

(1996): Varieties of supervenience. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 10, pp.221-42.
@

Stalnaker, R.

(1999): Context and Content: Essays on Intentionality in Speech and Thought . Oxford University Press.
@

Stalnaker, R.

(2001): On considering a possible world as actual. In: '2001 '.
@

Stalnaker, R.

(2004): Lewis on intentionality. In: ' Australian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 82, pp.199-212.
@

Stalnaker, R. C.

(1989): On what's in the head. In: ' Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 3, pp.287-319.
@

Stalnaker, R. C.

(1990): Mental content and linguistic form. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 58, pp.129-46.
@

Stalnaker, R. C.

(1990): Narrow content. In: C. A. Anderson; J. Owens (Ed.): ' Propositional Attitudes'. CSLI.
@

Stampe, D.

(1977): Towards a causal theory of linguistic representation. In: 'Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 2, pp.42-63.
@

Stampe, D.

(1986): Verificationism and a causal account of meaning. In: ' Synthese', vol. 69, pp.107-37.
@

Stampe, D.

(1991): Content, context, and explanation. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): ' Information, Semantics, and Epistemology'. Blackwell.
@

Stampe, D. W.

(1986): Defining desire. In: J. Marks (Ed.): 'The Ways of Desire '. Precedent.
@

Stampe, D. W.

(1987): The authority of desire. In: 'Philosophical Review b ', vol. 96, pp.335-81.
@

Stampe, D. W.

(1994): Desire. In: S. Guttenplan (Ed.): ' A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Stampe, D. W.; Gibson, M. I.

(1992): Of one's own free will. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 52, pp.529-56.
@

Stanton, W. L.

(1983): Supervenience and psychophysical law in anomalous monism. In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 64, pp.72-9.
@

Steiling, K.

(1976): The elimination of sensations and the loss of philosophy. In: 'Auslegung', vol. 3, pp.20-28.
@

Stein, E.

(1994): Rationality and reflective equilibrium. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 99, pp.137-72.
@

Stein, E.

(1996): Without Good Reason: The Rationality Debate in Philosophy and Cognitive Science. Oxford University Press.
@

Steinhart, E.

(2001): Persons versus brains: Biological intelligence in human organisms . In: 'Biology and Philosophy', vol. 16, pp.3-27.
@

Stemmer, N.

(1987): The hypothesis of other minds: Is it the best explanation?. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 51, pp.109-121.
@

Stemmer, N.

(1993): Behavioral materialism, the success of folk psychology, and the first-person case. In: ' Behavior and Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.1-14.
@

Stemmer, N.

(1995): A behaviorist account to theory and simulation theories of folk psychology. In: 'Behavior and Philosophy ', vol. 23, pp.29-41.
@

Stemmer, N.

(2001): The mind-body problem and Quine's repudiation theory. In: 'Behavior And Philosophy', vol. 29, pp.187-202.
@

Stephan, A.

(1992): Emergence -- a systematic look at its historical facets. In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism'. De Gruyter.
@

Stephan, A.

(1997): Armchair arguments against emergence. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 46, pp.305-14.
@

Stephan, A.

(1999): Are animals capable of concepts?. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 51, pp.583-596.
@

Stephan, A.

(2001): How to lose the mind-body problem. In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 61, pp.279-283.
@

Stephens, G. L.; Graham, G.

(2004): Reconceiving delusions. In: ' International Review of Psychiatry,', vol. 16, pp.236-241.
@

Stephens, G. L.; Graham, G.

(2005): The delusional stance. In: M. Chung; K. Fulford and G. Graham (Ed.): 'The Philosophical Understanding of Schizophrenia'. Oxford University Press.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1983): Mental representation: What language is Brainese?. In: 'Philosophical Studies,', vol. 43, pp.365-82.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1986): The imagery debate. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 53, pp.560-83.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1989): Computational functional psychology: problems and prospects. In: P. Slezak (Ed.): 'Computers, Brains and Minds'. Kluwer.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1989): Fodor's nativism. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 55, pp.119-41.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1990): Animals and individualism. In: P. Hanson (Ed.): ' Information, Language and Cognition'. University of British Columbia Press.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1990): The Representational Theory of Mind. Blackwell.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1990): Connectionism. In: 'The Representational Theory of Mind '.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1990): Animals and individualism. In: P. Hanson (Ed.): ' Information, Language and Cognition'. University of British Columbia Press.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1993): Refuting eliminative materialism on the cheap?. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 8, pp.306-15.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1995): Basic minds. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp.251-70.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1995): Basic minds. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 9, pp.251-70.
@

Sterelny, K.

(1998): Intentional agency and the metarepresentation hypothesis. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.11-28.
@

Sterelny, K.

(2003): Thought in a Hostile World. Blackwell.
@

Sterelny, K.

(2003): Darwinian concepts in the philosophy of mind. In: J. Hodges; G. Radick (Ed.): 'The Cambridge Companion to Darwin'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Sterelny, K.

(2005): Externalism, epistemic artefacts and the extended mind. In: R. Schantz (Ed.): 'The Externalist Challenge: New Studies on Cognition and Intentionality'. de Gruyter.
@

Stern, D. G.

(1991): Models of memory: Wittgenstein and cognitive science. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 4, pp.203-18.
@

Sterrett, S. G.

(2000): Turing's two tests for intelligence. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 10, pp.541-559.
@

Steup, M.

(2003): Two forms of antiskepticism. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): ' New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Stevenson, J. G.

(1976): On the imitation game. In: 'Philosophia ', vol. 6, pp.131-33.
@

Stevenson, J. T.

(1960): `Sensations and brain processes': A reply to J. J. C. Smart . In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 69, pp.505-10.
@

Stevenson, L.

(2003): Twelve conceptions of imagination. In: ' British Journal of Aesthetics', vol. 43, pp.238-59.
@

Steward, H.

(1997): The Ontology of Mind: Events, Processes, and States. Oxford University Press.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1975): Innate Ideas. University of California Press.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1978): Beliefs and subdoxastic states. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 45, pp.499-518.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1978): Autonomous psychology and the belief/desire thesis. In: 'Monist', vol. 61, pp.573-91.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1978): Do animals have beliefs?. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 57, pp.15-28.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1979): Between Chomskian rationalism and Popperian empiricism. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 30, pp.329-47.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1980): Headaches. In: 'Philosophical Books ', vol. 21, pp.65-73.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1981): Dennett on intentional systems. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 12, pp.39-62.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1982): On the ascription of content. In: A. Woodfield (Ed.): ' Thought and Object'. Oxford University Press.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1983): Some evidence against narrow causal theories of belief. In: 'From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science'.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1983): From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. MIT Press.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1984): Relativism, rationality, and the limits of intentional ascription . In: '1984'.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1985): Could man be an irrational animal?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 64, pp.115-35.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1991): Do true believers exist?. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 65, pp.229-44.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1991): Narrow content meets fat syntax. In: B. Loewer; G. Rey (Ed.): 'Meaning in Mind: Fodor and his Critics'. Blackwell.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1992): What is a theory of mental representation?. In: 'Mind ', vol. 101, pp.243-61.
@

Stich, S. P.

(1996): Deconstructing the mind. In: 'Deconstructing the Mind '.
@

Stich, S. P.; Nichols, S.

(1993): Folk psychology: simulation or tacit theory?. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 7, pp.35-71.
@

Stich, S. P.; Nichols, S.

(1995): Second thoughts on simulation. In: M. Davies; T. Stone (Ed.): 'Mental Simulation'. Blackwell.
@

Stich, S. P.; Nichols, S.

(1997): Cognitive penetrability, rationality, and restricted simulation. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp.297-326.
@

Stich, S. P.; Ravenscroft, R.

(1994): What is folk psychology?. In: ' Cognition', vol. 50, pp.447-68.
@

Stich, S. P.; and Laurence, S.

(1994): Intentionality and naturalism. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.159-82.
@

Stich, S.; Nichols, S.

(1998): Theory theory to the max. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.421-449.
@

Stich, S.; Nichols, S.

(2002): Folk psychology. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): 'Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Stich, S.; Warfield, T.

(1995): Reply to Clark and Smolensky: Do connectionist minds have beliefs?. In: C. Macdonald (Ed.): ' Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation'. Blackwell.
@

Sticklen, J.

(1989): Problem-solving architectures at the knowledge level. In: 'Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence', vol. 1, pp.233-247.
@

Stock, G.

(1988): Leibniz and Kripke's sceptical paradox. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 38, pp.326-329.
@

Stocker, M.

(2004): Some considerations about intellectual desire and emotions. In: R. Solomon (Ed.): 'Thinking about Feeling: Contemporary Philosophers on Emotions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Stoljar, D.; Gold, S.

(1998): On biological and cognitive neuroscience. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 13, pp.110-31.
@

Stone, J.

(1988): Parfit and the Buddha: Why there are no people. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 48, pp.519-32.
@

Stone, J.

(1998): Free will as a gift from God. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 92, pp.257-81.
@

Stone, J.

(2005): Why there are still no people. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 70.
@

Stone, T.; Davies, M.

(1993): Cognitive neuropsychology and the philosophy of mind. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 44, pp.589-622.
@

Stone, T.; Davies, M.

(1996): The mental simulation debate: A progress report. In: P. Carruthers; P. Smith (Ed.): 'Theories of Theories of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Stone, T.; Young, A.

(1997): Delusions and brain injury: The philosophy and psychology of belief. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 12, pp.327-64.
@

Stoneham, T.

(1998): On believing that I am thinking. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 98, pp.125-44.
@

Stoneham, T.

(1999): Boghossian on empty natural kind concepts. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 99, pp.119-22.
@

Stoneham, T.

(2003): Temporal externalism. In: 'Philosophical Papers ', vol. 1, pp.97-107.
@

Stoneham, T.

(2003): Conditionals and biconditionals in constitutive theories of self-knowledge. In: 'Philosophical Papers ', vol. 32, pp.149-55.
@

Storl, H.

(1992): The problematic nature of parfitian persons. In: ' Personalist Forum', vol. 8, pp.123-31.
@

Stotz, K. C.; Griffiths, P. E.

(2002): Dancing in the dark: Evolutionary psychology and the argument from design. In: S. Scher; F. Rauscher (Ed.): 'Evolutionary Psychology: Alternative Approaches'. Kluwer.
@

Stout, R.

(2002): What you know when you know how someone behaves. In: ' Electronic Journal of Anlaytic Philosophy', vol. 7.
@

Stout, R.

(2003): Behaviourism. In: 'Think', vol. 5.
@

Stoutland, F.

(1971): Ontological simplicity and the identity hypothesis. In: '1971'.
@

Strasser, M.

(1988): Frankfurt, Aristotle, and PAP. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 26, pp.235-46.
@

Strawson, G.

(1986): Freedom and Belief. Oxford University Press.
@

Strawson, G.

(1989): Consciousness, free will, and the unimportance of determinism. In: 'Inquiry', vol. 32, pp.3-27.
@

Strawson, G.

(1989): Red and `red'. In: 'Synthese', vol. 78, pp.193-232.
@

Strawson, G.

(1994): The impossibility of moral responsibility. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 75, pp.5-24.
@

Strawson, G.

(2000): The unhelpfulness of determinism. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 60, pp.149-56.
@

Strawson, G.

(2002): The bounds of freedom. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Strawson, G.

(2002): Dreams of final responsibility. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Strawson, G.

(2004): Real intentionality. In: ' Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences', vol. 3, pp.287-313.
@

Strawson, G.

(2004): Against narrativity. In: 'Ration', vol. 17.
@

Strawson, P.

(1958): Persons. In: ' Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science', vol. 2, pp.330-53.
@

Strawson, P. F.

(1962): Freedom and resentment. In: ' Proceedings of the British Academy', vol. 48, pp.1-25.
@

Stroud, B.

(1965): Wittgenstein and logical necessity. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 74, pp.504-518.
@

Stroud, B.

(1996): Mind, meaning and practice. In: H. Sluga; D. Stern (Ed.): ' The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Stroud, B.

(2000): The Quest for Reality: Subjectivism and the Metaphysics of Colour . Oxford University Press.
@

Stroud, B.

(2003): Anti-individualism and scepticism. In: M. Hahn; B. Ramberg (Ed.): 'Reflections and Replies'. MIT Press.
@

Stroud-Drinkwater, C.

(1994): The naive theory of color. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 54, pp.345-54.
@

Stubenberg, L.

(1992): What is it like to be Oscar?. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 90, pp.1-26.
@

Stueber, K.

(2002): The problem of self-knowledge. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 56, pp.269-96.
@

Stueber, K. R.

(2005): Mental causation and the paradoxes of explanation. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 122, pp.243-77.
@

Stufflebeam, R. S.

(2001): Brain matters: A case against representations in the brain . In: W. Bechtel; P. Mandik; J. Mundale; and R. Stufflebeam (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader '. Blackwell.
@

Stufflebeam, R. S.; Bechtel, W.

(1997): PET: Exploring the myth and the method. In: 'Philsophy of Science', vol. 64, pp.95-106.
@

Stump, E.

(1990): Intellect, will, and the principle of alternative possibilities. In: M. Beaty (Ed.): 'Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy'. University of Notre Dame Press.
@

Stump, E.

(1996): Persons, identification, and freedom. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 24, pp.183-214.
@

Stump, E.

(1999): Alternative pssibilities and moral responsibility: The flicker of freedom . In: 'Journal of Ethics', vol. 3, pp.299-324.
@

Stump, E.; Fischer, J.

(2000): Transfer principles and moral responsibility. In: 'Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.47-56.
@

Sturdee, D.

(1997): The semantic shuffle: Shifting emphasis in Dretske's account of representational content. In: ' Erkenntnis', vol. 47, pp.89-104.
@

Sturgeon, S.

(1994): Good reasoning and cognitive architecture. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 9, pp.88-101.
@

Sturgeon, S.

(1998): Physicalism and overdetermination. In: 'Mind ', vol. 107, pp.411-432.
@

Sturgeon, S.

(2001): The roots of reductionism. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Suber, P.

(1988): What is software?. In: 'Journal of Speculative Philosophy ', vol. 2, pp.89-119.
@

Sufka, K. J.; Lynch, M. P.

(2000): Sensations and pain processes. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.299-311.
@

Suits, D.

(1989): Out of the Chinese Room. In: ' Computing and Philosophy Newsletter', vol. 4, pp.1-7.
@

Sullivan, S. R.

(1993): From natural function to indeterminate content. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 69, pp.129-37.
@

Summerfield, D. M.

(1990): Philosophical Investigations 201: A Wittgensteinian reply to Kripke. In: ' Journal of the History of Philosophy', vol. 28.
@

Summerfield, D. M.

(1990): On taking the rabbit of rule-following out of the hat of representation: A response to Pettit's 'The reality of rule-following' . In: 'Mind', vol. 99.
@

Sun, R.

(2000): Symbol grounding: a new look at an old idea. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.149-172.
@

Suppes, P.

(1985): Davidson's views on psychology as a science. In: B. Vermazen; M. Hintikka (Ed.): 'Essays on Davidson'. Oxford University Press.
@

Sussman, A.

(1981): Reflection on the chances for a scientific dualism. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 78, pp.95-118.
@

Suster, D.

(2001): Semifactuals and epiphenomenalism. In: 'Acta Analytica ', vol. 16, pp.23-43.
@

Suter, R.

(1986): Saul Wittgenstein's skeptical paradox. In: ' Philosophical Research Archives', vol. 12.
@

Sutton, J.

(1998): Philosophy and Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism. Cambridge University Press.
@

Sutton, J.

(2003): Memory. In: '2003'.
@

Sutton, J.

(2004): Are concepts mental representations or abstracta?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 68, pp.89-108.
@

Sutton, J.

(2004): Representation, reduction, and interdisciplinarity in the sciences of memory. In: H. Clapin (Ed.): ' Representation in Mind'. Elsevier.
@

Swanton, C.

(1992): Freedom: A Coherence Theory. Hackett.
@

Swartz, N.

(1974): Can the theory of contingent identity between sensation-states and brain-states be made empirical?. In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 3, pp.405-17.
@

Swinburne, R.

(1993): Are mental events identical with brain events?. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 19, pp.173-181.
@

Szasz, T.

(2002): The Meaning of Mind: Language, Morality, and Neuroscience. Syracuse University Press.
@

Szubka, T.

(2000): Meaning rationalism, a priori, and transparency of content. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.491-503.

T


@

Tait, W. W.

(1986): Wittgenstein and the 'skeptical paradoxes'. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 9, pp.475-488.
@

Tait, W. W.

(2002): The myth of the mind. In: 'Topoi ', vol. 21, pp.65-74.
@

Talbott, T.

(1988): On free agency and the concept of power. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 69, pp.241-54.
@

Talmage, C. J. L.

(1998): Semantic localism and the locality of content. In: 'Erkenntnis', vol. 48.
@

Talmage, C. J. L.; Mercer, M.

(1991): Meaning holism and interpretability. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 41, pp.301-15.
@

Tanney, J.

(1996): A constructivist picture of self-knowledge. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 71, pp.4-5.
@

Tanney, J.

(1999): Normativity and judgment II. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 73, pp.45-61.
@

Tanney, J.

(2000): Playing the rule-following game. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 75.
@

Tanney, J.

(2003): Self-knowledge, normativity, and construction. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): 'Logic, Thought, and Language'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Tappolet, C.

(2002): Long-term emotions and emotional experiences in the explanation of actions. In: ' European Review of Philosophy', vol. 5, pp.151-161.
@

Taylor, C.

(1967): Mind-body identity, a side issue?. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 76, pp.201-13.
@

Taylor, C.; Dennett, D. C.

(2002): Who's afraid of determinism? Rethinking causes and possibilities. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Taylor, G.

(1975): Justifying the emotions. In: '1975'.
@

Taylor, J. G.

(2003): Do virtual actions avoid the Chinese room?. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence'. Oxford University Press.
@

Taylor, K.

(1987): Belief, information and semantic content: A naturalist's lament. In: 'Synthese', vol. 71, pp.97-124.
@

Taylor, K.

(1989): Supervenience and levels of meaning. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 27, pp.443-58.
@

Taylor, K.

(1989): Narrow content functionalism and the mind-body problem. In: 'Nous', vol. 23, pp.355-72.
@

Taylor, K. A.

(1994): How not to refute eliminative materialism. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 7, pp.101-125.
@

Teghrarian, S.

(1994): Wittgenstein, Kripke, and the "paradox" of meaning. Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy. In: '1994 '.
@

Tegtmeier, E.

(2005): Intentionality is not representation. In: 'Metaphysica ', vol. 6, no.1, pp.77-84.
@

Teichmann, J.

(1967): The contingent identity of minds and brains. In: 'Mind ', vol. 76, pp.404-15.
@

Teichmann, R.

(1992): Whyte on the individuation of desires. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 52, pp.103-7.
@

Teller, P.

(1984): The poor man's guide to supervenience and determination. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 22, pp.137-62.
@

Teller, P.

(1985): Is supervenience just disguised reduction?. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 23, pp.93-100.
@

Teller, P.

(1992): A contemporary look at emergence. In: A. Beckermann; H. Flohr; J. Kim (Ed.): 'Emergence or Reduction?: Prospects for Nonreductive Physicalism'. De Gruyter.
@

Temkin, J.

(1986): A private language argument. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 24.
@

Temkin, J.

(1990): Wittgenstein on criteria and other minds. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 28, pp.561-93.
@

Ten Elshof, G.

(1997): Supervenient difficulties with nonreductive physicalism: A critical analysis of supervenience physicalism. In: 'Kinesis', vol. 24, pp.3-22.
@

Teng, N. Y.

(1999): The language of thought and the embodied nature of language use. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 94, pp.237-251.
@

Teng, N. Y.

(2000): A cognitive analysis of the Chinese room argument. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 13, pp.313-24.
@

Thagard, P.

(1986): The emergence of meaning: An escape from Searle's Chinese Room. In: 'Behaviorism', vol. 14, pp.139-46.
@

Thagard, P.

(1986): Parallel computation and the mind-body problem. In: ' Cognitive Science', vol. 10, pp.301-18.
@

Thagard, P.

(1990): Concepts and conceptual change. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 82, pp.255-74.
@

Thagard, P.

(1990): Philosophy and machine learning. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 20, pp.261-76.
@

Thagard, P.

(1991): Philosophical and computational models of explanation. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 64, pp.87-104.
@

Thagard, P.

(2002): How molecules matter to mental computation. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 69, pp.497-518.
@

Thalberg, I.

(1964): Emotion and thought. In: '1964'.
@

Thalberg, I.

(1969): Other times, other places, other minds. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 20.
@

Thalberg, I.

(1978): A novel approach to mind-brain identity. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 3, pp.255-72.
@

Thomas, J.

(1996): Analogies and the mind of the replica: Sunburn, the little green bug, and the fake plant. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 46, pp.364-371.
@

Thomas, N. J. T.

(1997): Are theories of imagination theories of imagery.
@

Thomasson, A.

(1998): A nonreductivist solution to mental causation. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 89, pp.181-95.
@

Thompson, D.

(1965): Can a machine be conscious?. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 16.
@

Thompson, E.

(1995): Colour vision, evolution, and perceptual content. In: ' Synthese', vol. 104, pp.1-32.
@

Thompson, E.

(1995): Colour Vision. Routledge.
@

Thompson, E.; Palacios, A.; Varela, F. J.

(1992): Ways of coloring. In: ' 1992'.
@

Thomson, J. F.

(1951): The argument from analogy and the problem of other minds. In: 'Mind', vol. 60, pp.336-50.
@

Thomson, J. J.

(1969): The identity theory. In: S. Morgenbesser; P. Suppes; M. White (Ed.): 'Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel'. St.
@

Thornton, M.

(1990): Do We Have Free Will?. St.
@

Thorp, J.

(1980): Free Will: A Defense Against Neurophysiological Determinism. Routledge.
@

Thorp, J.

(1980): Free Will: A Defense against Neurophysiological Determinism. Routledge.
@

Tibbetts, P.

(1996): Residual dualism in computational theories of mind. In: 'Dialectica', vol. 50, pp.37-52.
@

Tibbetts, P.

(2004): The concept of voluntary motor control in the recent neuroscientific literature. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 141, pp.247-76.
@

Tienson, J.

(1990): Is this any way to be a realist?. In: '1990'.
@

Tienson, J.

(2002): Higher-order causation. In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 63, pp.89-101.
@

Tiffany, E. C.

(2001): The rational character of belief and the argument for mental anomalism. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 103, pp.258-314.
@

Tolliver, J. T.

(1996): Interior colors. In: 'Philosophical Topics ', vol. 22, pp.411-41.
@

Tomberlin, J.

(1965): About the identity theory. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 43, pp.295-99.
@

Tomberlin, J.

(1994): Whither Southern Fundamentalism?. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Truth and Rationality'. Ridgeview.
@

Tomberlin, J. E.

(1965): About the identity theory. In: ' Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 53, pp.295-9.
@

Tooby, J.; Cosmides, L.

(1998): Evolutionizing the cognitive sciences: A reply to Shapiro and Epstein. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 13, pp.195-204.
@

Tooley, M.

(2001): Functional concepts, referent ially opaque contexts, causal relations, and the definition of theoretical terms. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 105, pp.251-79.
@

Toribio, J.

(1997): Twin pleas: Probing content and compositionality. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 57, pp.871-89.
@

Toribio, J.

(1999): Meaning, dispositions, and normativity. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 9, pp.399-413.
@

Toribio, J.

(2002): Mindful belief: Accountability, expertise, and cognitive kinds. In: 'Theoria', vol. 68, pp.224-49.
@

Toribio, J.

(2002): Semantic responsibility. In: 'Philosophical Explorations ', vol. 1, pp.39-58.
@

Toribio, J.

(2003): Free belief. In: ' Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences', vol. 2, pp.327-36.
@

Toulmin, S.

(1977): Self-knowledge and knowledge of self. In: ' The Self: Psychological and Philosophical Issues'.
@

Traiger, S.

(2000): Making the right identification in the Turing test. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 10, pp.561-572.
@

Travis, C.

(2000): Unshadowed Thought: Representation in Thought and Language. Harvard University Press.
@

Trout, J. D.

(1991): Belief attribution in science: Folk psychology under theoretical stress . In: 'Synthese', vol. 87, pp.379-400.
@

Trusted, J.

(1984): Free Will and Responsibilty. Oxford University Press.
@

Tuomela, R.

(1989): Methodological solipsism and explanation in psychology. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 56, pp.23-47.
@

Tuomela, R.

(1990): Can collectives have beliefs?. In: ' Acta Philosophica Fennica', vol. 49, pp.454-72.
@

Tuomela, R.

(1998): A defense of mental causation. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 90, pp.1-34.
@

Turing, A.

(1950): Computing machinery and intelligence. In: 'Mind ', vol. 59, pp.433-60.
@

Turvey, M. T.; Shaw, R. E.; Reed, E. S.; Mace, W. M.

(1981): Ecological laws of perceiving and acting: In Reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn. In: 'Cognition ', vol. 9, pp.237-304.
@

Tye, M.

(1983): Functionalism and type physicalism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 44, pp.161-74.
@

Tye, M.

(1984): The debate about mental imagery. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 81, pp.678-91.
@

Tye, M.

(1987): Representation in pictorialism and connectionism. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy Supplement', vol. 26, pp.163-184.
@

Tye, M.

(1988): The picture theory of images. In: '1988'.
@

Tye, M.

(1989): The Metaphysics of Mind. Cambridge University Press.
@

Tye, M.

(1991): The Imagery Debate.
@

Tye, M.

(1994): Naturalism and the problem of intentionality. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 19, pp.122-42.
@

Tye, M.

(1995): A representational theory of pains and their phenomenal character. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 9, pp.223-39.
@

Tye, M.

(1998): Externalism and memory. In: 'Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 72, pp.77-94.
@

Tye, M.

(2000): Consciousness, Color, and Content. MIT Press.
@

Tymoczko, T.

(1991): Why I am not a Turing Machine: Godel's theorem and the philosophy of mind. In: J. Garfield (Ed.): ' Foundations of Cognitive Science'. Paragon House.

U


@

Ullman, S.

(1980): Against direct perception. In: ' Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 3, pp.333-81.
@

Unger, P.

(1979): I do not exist. In: G. Macdonald (Ed.): ' Perception and Identity'. Cornell University Press.
@

Unger, P.

(1979): Why there are no people. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 4, pp.177-222.
@

Unger, P.

(1990): Identity, Consciousness, and Value. Oxford University Press.
@

Unger, P.

(2002): Free will and scientifiphicalism. In: '2002'.
@

Urmson, J. O.

(1971): Memory and imagination. In: 'Mind', vol. 80.
@

Usher, M.

(2001): A statistical referent ial theory of content: Using information theory to account for misrepresentation. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 16, pp.331-334.
@

Usher, M.

(2004): Comment on Ryder's SINBAD neurosemantics: Is teleofunction isomorphism the way to understand representations?. In: 'Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.241-248.
@

Uttal, W. R.

(2001): The New Phrenology: The Limits of Localizing Cognitive Processes in the Brain. MIT Press.
@

Uttal, W. R.

(2002): Functional brain mapping: What is it good for? Plenty, but not everything. In: 'Brain and Mind ', vol. 3, pp.375-79.

V


@

Vacariu, G.; Terhesiu, D.; Vacariu, M.

(2001): Toward a very idea of representation. In: 'Synthese', vol. 129, pp.275-295.
@

Vadas, M.

(1984): Affective and nonaffective desire. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 45, pp.273-80.
@

Vahid, H.

(2003): Content externalism and the internalism/externalism debate in justification theory. In: ' European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 11, pp.89-107.
@

Vaina, L. M.

(1990): What and where in the human visual system: Two hierarchies of visual modules. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 83, pp.49-91.
@

Vander-Laan, D.

(2001): A regress argument for restrictive incompatibilism. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 103, pp.201-215.
@

Vandervert, L. R.

(1991): On the modeling of emergent interaction: Which will it be, the laws of thermodynamics or Sperry's "wheel" in the subcircuitry? . In: 'Journal of Mind and Behavior', vol. 12, pp.535-39.
@

Varela, F.; Thompson, E.; Rosch, E.

(1991): The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. MIT Press.
@

Vaughan, R.

(1989): Searle's narrow content. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 2, pp.185-90.
@

Velleman, D.

(2000): On the aim of belief. In: '2000'.
@

Velmans, M.

(2003): Preconscious free will. In: ' Journal of Consciousness Studies', vol. 10, no.12, pp.42-61.
@

Vendler, Z.

(1981): Ryle's thoughts on thinking. In: ' Midwest Studies of Philosophy', vol. 6, pp.335-43.
@

Vera, A. H.; Simon, H. A.

(1993): Situated action: A symbolic interpretation. In: 'Cognitive Science', vol. 17, pp.7-48.
@

Vermazen, B.; Hintikka, M.

(1985): Essays on Davidson. Oxford University Press.
@

Vesey, G.

(1989): Responsibility and free will. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 24, pp.85-100.
@

Vesey, P.

(1974): Personal Identity: A Philosophical Analysis. Cornell University Press.
@

Vete, van de, D.

(1971): The problem of robot consciousness. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 32, pp.149-65.
@

Vicente, A.

(2001): Realization, determination and mental causation. In: ' Theoria', vol. 16, pp.77-94.
@

Vicente, A.

(2004): The overdetermination argument revisited. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 14, pp.331-47.
@

Viger, C.

(2000): Where do Dennett's stances stand? Explaining our kinds of minds. In: A. Brook; D. Ross; D. Thompson (Ed.): 'Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment'. MIT Press.
@

Viger, C.

(2005): Learning to think: A response to the language of thought argument for innateness. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 20, pp.313-25.
@

Viger, C. D.

(2001): Locking on to the language of thought. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.203-215.
@

Vignemont, de, F.

(2004): The co-consciousness hypothesis. In: ' Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences', vol. 3, pp.97-114.
@

Vihvelin, K.

(1988): The modal argument for incompatibilism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 53, pp.227-44.
@

Vihvelin, K.

(1991): Frrdon, causation, and counterfactuals. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 64, pp.161-84.
@

Vihvelin, K.

(2000): Freedom, foreknowledge, and the principle of alternate possibilities . In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 30, pp.1-23.
@

Vihvelin, K.

(2000): Libertarian compatibilism. In: ' Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.139-166.
@

Vincent, A.

(1989): Can groups be persons?. In: 'Review of Metaphysics ', vol. 42, pp.687-715.
@

Viney, D. W.; Crosby, D. A.

(1994): Free will in process perspective. In: ' New Ideas in Psychology', vol. 12, pp.129-41.
@

Vision, G.

(2001): Flash! Fodor splits the atom. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 61, pp.5-10.
@

Voltolini, A.

(2005): On the metaphysics of internalism and externalism. In: 'Disputation', vol. 18.
@

Von Eckardt, B.; Poland, J.

(2000): In defense of the standard view. In: ' Protosociology', vol. 14, pp.312-331.
@

Von Morstein, P.

(1980): Kripke, Wittgenstein and the private language argument. In: 'Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 11, pp.61-74.
@

Vries, de, W. A.

(1996): Experience and the swamp creature. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 82, pp.55-80.

W


@

Wagner, S.

(1996): Teleosemantics and the troubles of naturalism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 82, pp.81-110.
@

Wagner, S. J.

(1988): The liberal and the lycanthrope. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 69, pp.165-74.
@

Wakefield, J.

(2003): Fodor on inscrutability. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 18, pp.524-537.
@

Wakefield, J.

(2003): The Chinese room argument reconsidered: Essentialism, indeterminacy, and strong AI. In: ' Minds and Machines', vol. 13, pp.285-319.
@

Wakefield, J. C.

(2002): Broad versus narrow content in the explanation of action: Fodor on Frege cases. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 15, pp.119-33.
@

Walker, V.

(1990): In defense of a different taxonomy: A reply to Owens. In: 'Philosophical Review', vol. 99.
@

Wallace, J.; Mason, H. E.

(1990): On some thought experiments about mind and meaning . In: C. Anderson; J. Owens (Ed.): 'Propositional Attitudes'. CSLI.
@

Waller, B.

(1990): Freedom without Responsibility. Temple University Press.
@

Waller, B.

(2003): A metacompatibilist account of free will: Making compatibilists and incompatibilist more compatible. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 112, pp.209-224.
@

Waller, B. N.

(1989): Uneven starts and just deserts (fatalism and free will). In: 'Analysis', vol. 49, pp.209-13.
@

Wallis, C.

(1994): Using representation to explain. In: E. Dietrich (Ed.): ' Thinking Computers and Virtual Persons'. Academic Press.
@

Wallis, C.

(1994): Representation and the imperfect ideal. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 61, pp.407-28.
@

Wallis, C.

(1995): Asymmetric dependence, representation, and cognitive science. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 33, pp.373-401.
@

Walsh, D. M.

(1998): Wide content individualism. In: 'Mind ', vol. 107, pp.625-652.
@

Walsh, D. M.

(2001): Naturalism, Evolution and the Mind. Cambridge University Press.
@

Walsh, D. M.

(2002): Brentano's chestnuts. In: A. Ariew (Ed.): 'Functions'. Oxford University Press.
@

Walter, H.

(2001): Neurophilosophy of Free Will. MIT Press.
@

Walter, H.

(2002): Neurophilosophy of free will. In: R. Kane (Ed.): ' The Oxford Handbook on Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Walter, S.; Heckmann, H.

(2003): Physicalism and Mental Causation. Imprint Academic.
@

Walton, D.; Strongman, K. T.

(1998): Neonate Crusoes, the private language argument and psychology. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 11, pp.443-65.
@

Wang, H.

(1974): From Mathematics to Philosophy. London.
@

Ward, A.

(1989): Philosophical functionalism. In: 'Behaviorism ', vol. 17, pp.155-8.
@

Ward, A.

(2001): The compatibility of psychological naturalism and representationalism . In: 'Disputatio', vol. 11.
@

Warfield, T.

(1996): Determinism and moral responsiblity are incompatible. In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 24, pp.215-26.
@

Warfield, T.

(2000): Causal determinism and human freedom are incompatible: A new argument for incompatibilism. In: ' Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.167-180.
@

Warfield, T. A.

(1992): Privileged self-knowledge and externalism are compatible. In: 'Analysis', vol. 52, pp.232-37.
@

Warfield, T. A.

(1993): On a semantic argument against conceptual role semantics. In: 'Analysis', vol. 53, pp.298-304.
@

Warfield, T. A.

(1993): Folk-psychological ceteris-paribus laws. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 71, pp.99-112.
@

Warfield, T. A.

(1994): Fodorian semantics: A reply to Adams and Aizawa. In: 'Minds and Machines', vol. 4, pp.205-14.
@

Warfield, T. A.

(1995): Knowing the world and knowing our minds. In: '1995 '.
@

Warfield, T. A.

(1997): Externalism, privileged self-knowledge, and the irrelevance of slow switching. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 57, pp.282-84.
@

Warmbrod, K.

(1989): Beliefs and sentences in the head. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 2, pp.201-30.
@

Warmbrod, K.

(1992): Primitive representation and misrepresentation. In: ' Topoi', vol. 11, pp.89-101.
@

Warnock, M.

(1987): Memory. Faber.
@

Waskan, J.

(2003): Folk psychology and the gauntlet of irrealism. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 41, pp.627-656.
@

Waskan, J.; Bechtel, W.

(1997): Directions in connectionist research: Tractable computations without syntactically structured representations. In: 'Metaphilosophy', vol. 28, pp.31-62.
@

Wason, P.

(1966): Reasoning. In: Foss (Ed.): 'New Horizons in Psychology'. Penguin.
@

Waterman, C.

(1995): The Turing test and the argument from analogy for other minds. In: 'Southwest Philosophy Review', vol. 11, pp.15-22.
@

Watkins, J. W. N.

(1978): A basic difficulty in the mind-brain identity hypothesis. In: J. Eccles (Ed.): 'Mind and Brain'. Paragon House.
@

Watkins, M.

(1999): Do animals see colors? An anthropocentrist's guide to animals, the color blind, and far away places. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 94, pp.189-209.
@

Watkins, M.

(2005): Seeing red: The metaphysics of colours without the physics. In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 83, pp.33-52.
@

Watson, G.

(1975): Free agency. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 72, pp.205-20.
@

Watson, G.

(1982): Free Will. Oxford University Press.
@

Watson, G.

(1987): Free action and free will. In: 'Mind ', vol. 96, pp.154-72.
@

Watt, D.

(2002): Commentary on Professor Hobson's first-person account of a lateral medullary stroke (CVA): Affirmative action for the brainstem in consciousness studies? . In: 'Consciousness and Cognition', vol. 11, pp.391-395.
@

Watt, S.

(1996): Naive psychology and the inverted Turing test. In: ' Psycoloquy', vol. 7, no.14.
@

Weatherall, P.

(1996): What do propositions measure in folk psychology?. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 9, pp.365-80.
@

Webb, J.

(1968): Metamathematics and the philosophy of mind. In: ' Philosophy of Science', vol. 35, pp.156-78.
@

Webb, J.

(1980): Mechanism, Mentalism and Metamathematics. Kluwer.
@

Webb, S.

(1994): Witnessed behavior and Dennett's intentional stance. In: ' Philosophical Topics', vol. 22, pp.457-70.
@

Weber, B.; Depew, D.

(2003): Evolution and Learning: The Baldwin Effect Reconsidered . MIT Press.
@

Webster, W. R.

(2002): Wavelength theory of color strikes back: The return of the physical . In: 'Synthese', vol. 132, pp.303-34.
@

Webster, W. R.

(2003): Revelation and transparency in colour vision refuted: A case of mind/brain identity and another bridge over the explanatory gap . In: 'Synthese', vol. 133, pp.419-39.
@

Weckert, J.

(1990): Functionalism's impotence. In: 'Philosophical Inquiry ', vol. 32.
@

Wedgwood, R.

(2000): The price of non-reductive physicalism. In: 'Nous ', vol. 34, pp.400-421.
@

Wedgwood, R.

(2002): The aim of belief. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 16, pp.267-97.
@

Wegner, D.

(2003): The Illusion of Conscious Will. MIT Press.
@

Wegner, D.

(2004): Precis of The Illusion of Conscious Will (and commentaries and reply) . In: 'Behavioral and Brain Sciences', vol. 27.
@

Weinberg, J.

(1946): Our knowledge of other minds. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 60.
@

Weinzweig, M.

(1962): Our knowledge of other minds: a pseudo-problem?. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 23, pp.250-255.
@

Weir, A.

(2001): More trouble for functionalism. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 101, pp.267-94.
@

Weir, A.

(2001): More trouble for functionalism. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 101, pp.267-293.
@

Weir, A.

(2003): Objective content. In: 'Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 77, pp.47-72.
@

Weiskopf, D.

(2004): The place of time in cognition. In: ' The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 55, pp.87-105.
@

Weiskopf, D; Bechtel, W.

(2004): Remarks on Fodor on having concepts. In: ' Mind and Language', vol. 19, pp.48-56.
@

Weismann, D.

(1965): A note on the identity thesis. In: 'Mind ', vol. 74, pp.571-77.
@

Weiss, T.

(1990): Closing the Chinese room. In: 'Ratio ', vol. 3, pp.165-81.
@

Weitz, M.

(1951): Professor Ryle's "logical behaviourism". In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 48, pp.297-300.
@

Weitz, M.

(1988): Theories of Concepts: A History of the Major Philosophical Traditions . Routledge.
@

Weitzman, L.

(1996): What makes a causal theory of content anti-skeptical?. In: 'Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 56, pp.299-318.
@

Welch, P. D.

(2004): On the possibility, or otherwise, of hypercomputation. In: 'British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 55.
@

Weller, C.

(1997): Bonjour and mentalese. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 113, pp.251-63.
@

Wellman, C.

(1961): Our criteria for third-person psychological sentences. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 58, pp.281-93.
@

Wells, A.

(1996): Situated action, symbol systems and universal computation. In: 'Minds & Machines', vol. 6, pp.33-46.
@

Welshon, R.

(1999): Anomalous monism and epiphenomenalism. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 80, pp.103-120.
@

Welshon, R.

(2002): Emergence, realization, and supervenience. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 108, pp.39-51.
@

Werhane, P.

(1992): Skepticism, Rules and Private Languages. Humanities Press.
@

Westcott, M. R.

(1977): Free will: An exercise in metaphysical truth or psychological consequences. In: ' Canadian Psychological Review', vol. 18, pp.249-63.
@

Westphal, J.

(1982): Brown: Remarks on color. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 25, pp.417-33.
@

Westphal, J.

(1986): White. In: 'Mind', vol. 95, pp.310-28.
@

Westphal, J.

(1989): Black. In: 'Mind', vol. 98, pp.585-9.
@

Westphal, J.

(1991): Colour: A Philosophical Introduction. Blackwell.
@

Westphal, M.; Bonanno, G.

(2004): Emotion self-regulation. In: S. Moore; M. Oaksford (Ed.): 'Consciousness, Emotional Self-Regulation and the Brain'. John Benjamins.
@

Wheeler, M.

(2003): Changes in the rules: Computers, dynamic systems, and Searle. In: J. Preston; M. Bishop (Ed.): 'Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence '. Oxford University Press.
@

Wheeler, M.; Atkinson, A. P.

(2001): Domains, brains and evolution. In: D. Walsh (Ed.): 'Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Whitby, B.

(1996): The Turing test: AI's biggest blind alley?. In: P. Millican; A. Clark (Ed.): 'Machines and Thought'. Oxford University Press.
@

White, I.

(2001): A mind without a world within. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 101, pp.385-91.
@

White, M.

(1993): The Question of Free Will: A Holistic View. Princeton University Press.
@

White, S.

(1982): Partial character and the language of thought. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 63, pp.347-65.
@

White, S.

(1989): Metapsychological relativism and the self. In: ' Journal of Philosophy', vol. 86, pp.298-323.
@

White, S.

(1992): Narrow content and narrow interpretation. In: ' The Unity of the Self'.
@

White, S.

(2004): Skepticism, deflation and the rediscovery of the self. In: 'Monist', vol. 87.
@

Whitely, C.

(1962): Minds, machines and Godel: A reply to Mr. Lucas. In: ' Philosophy', vol. 37, pp.61-62.
@

Whitely, C. A.

(1961): Behaviourism. In: 'Mind', vol. 70, pp.164-74.
@

Whitely, C. H.

(1970): The mind-brain identity hypothesis. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 20, pp.193-99.
@

Whiten, A.

(2001): Theory of mind in non-verbal apes: Conceptual issues and the critical experiments. In: D. Walsh (Ed.): ' Evolution, Naturalism and Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Whiting, J.

(1986): Friends and future selves. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 95, pp.547-80.
@

Whitmer, J. M.

(1983): Intentionality, artificial intelligence, and the causal powers of the brain. In: 'Auslegung ', vol. 10, pp.194-210.
@

Whitmyer, VG.

(1999): Ecological color. In: 'Philosophical Psychology ', vol. 12, pp.197-214.
@

Whyte, J. T.

(1992): Weak-kneed desires. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 52, pp.107-11.
@

Widerker, D.

(1987): On an argument for incompatibilism. In: 'Analysis ', vol. 47, pp.37-41.
@

Widerker, D.

(1995): Libertarianism and Frankfurt's attack on the principle f alternative possibilities. In: ' Philosophical Review', vol. 104, pp.247-61.
@

Widerker, D.

(2000): Frankfurt's attack on the principle of alternative possibilities: A further look. In: ' Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.181-202.
@

Widerker, D.

(2002): Responsibility and Frankfurt-type examples. In: R. Kane (Ed.): 'The Oxford Handbook of Free Will'. Oxford University Press.
@

Wiggins, D.

(1987): The person as object of science, as subject of experience, and as locus of value. In: A. Peacocke; G. Gillett (Ed.): 'Persons and Personality'. Blackwell.
@

Wikforss, A.

(2001): Social externalism and conceptual errors. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 203, pp.217-31.
@

Wikforss, A.

(2004): Direct knowledge and other minds. (Plus reply by John McDowell) . In: 'Theoria', vol. 70.
@

Wikforss, A. M.

(2001): Semantic normativity. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 102, pp.203-26.
@

Wikforss, A. M.

(2005): Naming natural kinds. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 145, pp.65-87.
@

Wilcox, S.; Katz, S.

(1981): A direct realist alternative to the traditional conception of memory. In: 'Behaviorism ', vol. 9, pp.227-40.
@

Wilder, H.

(1996): Interpretative cognitive ethology. In: C. Allen; D. Jamison (Ed.): 'Readings in Animal Cognition'. MIT Press.
@

Wilkerson, W. S.

(1997): Real patterns and real problems: Making Dennett respectable on patterns and beliefs. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 97, pp.557-70.
@

Wilkerson, W. S.

(1999): From bodily motions to bodily intentions: the perception of bodily activity. In: ' Philosophical Psychology', vol. 12, pp.61-77.
@

Wilkerson, W. S.

(2001): Simulation, theory, and the frame problem: the interpretive moment . In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 14, pp.141-153.
@

Wilkes, K. V.

(1973): Physicalism. Routledge and Kegan Paul.
@

Wilkes, K. V.

(1981): Functionalism, psychology and the philosophy of mind. In: 'Philosophical Topics', vol. 12, pp.147-67.
@

Wilkes, K. V.

(1981): Multiple personalty and personal identity. In: ' British Journal for the Philosophy of Science', vol. 32, pp.331-48.
@

Wilkes, K. V.

(1984): Pragmatics in science and theory in common sense. In: 'Inquiry', vol. 27, pp.339-61.
@

Wilkes, K. V.

(1988): Real People: Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press.
@

Wilkes, K. V.

(1991): How many selves make me?. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 66, pp.235-43.
@

Wilkes, K. V.

(1991): The relationship between scientific psychology and common-sense psychology. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 89, pp.15-39.
@

Wilkes, K. V.

(1991): The long past and the short history. In: R. Bogdan (Ed.): 'Mind and Common Sense'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Wilkinson, S.

(2000): Is 'normal grief' a mental disorder?. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 50, pp.289-305.
@

Wilks, Y.

(1982): Some thoughts on procedural semantics. In: W. Lehnert (Ed.): ' Strategies for Natural Language Processing'. Lawrence Erlbaum.
@

Wilks, Y.

(1990): Form and content in semantics. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 82, pp.329-51.
@

Williams, B.

(1957): Personal identity and individuation. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 67, pp.229-52.
@

Williams, B.

(1959): Pleasure and belief. In: '1959'.
@

Williams, B.

(1973): Problems of the Self. Cambridge University Press.
@

Williams, C.

(1980): Free Will and Determinism: A Dialogue. Hackett.
@

Williams, M.

(1983): Wittgenstein on representation, privileged objects and private language . In: 'Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 13, pp.57-78.
@

Williams, M.

(1990): Social norms and narrow content. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 15, pp.425-462.
@

Williams, M.

(1990): Externalism and the philosophy of mind. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 40, pp.352-80.
@

Williams, M.

(1991): Blind obedience: Rules, community and the individual. In: K. Puhl (Ed.): 'Meaning Scepticism'. De Gruyter.
@

Williamson, T.

(1998): The broadness of the mental: Some logical issues. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives', vol. 12, pp.389-410.
@

Wilson, D. S.; Dietrich, E.; Clark, A. B.

(2003): On the inappropriate use of the naturalistic fallacy in evolutionary psychology. In: ' Biology and Philosophy', vol. 18, pp.669-81.
@

Wilson, G. M.

(1994): Kripke on Wittgenstein and normativity. In: ' Midwest Studies in Philosophy', vol. 19.
@

Wilson, G. M.

(1998): Semantic realism and Kripke's Wittgenstein. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 58, pp.99-122.
@

Wilson, J. M.

(1999): How superduper does a physicalist supervenience need to be?. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 49, pp.33-52.
@

Wilson, J. M.

(2002): Causal powers, forces, and superdupervenience. In: ' Grazer Philosophische Studien', vol. 63, pp.53-77.
@

Wilson, J. R. S.

(1972): Emotion and Object. Cambridge University Press.
@

Wilson, M.

(1985): What is this thing called `pain'? -- The philosophy of science behind the contemporary debate. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 66, pp.227-67.
@

Wilson, M. D.

(1995): Animal ideas. In: ' Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association', vol. 69, pp.7-25.
@

Wilson, R.

(2002): Individualism. In: S. Stich; T. Warfield (Ed.): ' Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind'. Blackwell.
@

Wilson, R. A.

(1992): Individualism, causal powers, and explanation. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 68, pp.103-39.
@

Wilson, R. A.

(1993): Against a priori arguments for individualism. In: ' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 74, pp.60-79.
@

Wilson, R. A.

(1994): Causal depth, theoretical appropriateness, and individualism in psychology. In: 'Philosophy of Science ', vol. 61, pp.55-75.
@

Wilson, R. A.

(1994): Wide computationalism. In: 'Mind ', vol. 103, pp.351-72.
@

Wilson, R. A.

(1995): Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind. Cambridge University Press.
@

Wilson, R. A.

(2001): Two views of realization. In: 'Philosophical Studies ', vol. 104, pp.1-31.
@

Wilton, R.

(2000): Consciousness, Free Will, and the Explanation of Human Behavior. E.
@

Wimsatt, W.

(1976): Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem. In: G. Globus (Ed.): 'Consciousness and the Brain'. Plenum Press.
@

Wimsatt, W. C.

(1997): Aggregativity: Reductive heuristics for finding emergence. In: 'Philosophy of Science', vol. 64, pp.372-84.
@

Winch, P.

(1983): Critical Study: Facts and Superfacts. In: ' The Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 33, pp.398-404.
@

Winograd, T.

(1985): Moving the semantic fulcrum. In: ' Linguistics and Philosophy', vol. 8, pp.91-104.
@

Winograd, T.

(1987): Cognition, attunement and modularity. In: '1987'.
@

Winograd, T.; Flores, F.

(1987): Understanding Computers and Cognition. Addison-Wesley.
@

Wisdom, J.

(1946): Other minds. In: 'Aristotelian Society Supplement ', vol. 20, pp.122-47.
@

Wisdom, J.

(1950): The concept of mind. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 50, pp.189-204.
@

Wisdom, J.

(1968): Other Minds. University of California Press.
@

Witmer, D. G.

(1998): What is wrong with the manifestability argument for supervenience? . In: 'Australasian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 76, pp.84-89.
@

Witmer, D. G.

(1999): Supervenience physicalism and the problem of extras. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 37, pp.315-31.
@

Witmer, D. G.

(2001): Sufficiency claims and physicalism: A formulation. In: C. Gillett; B. Loewer (Ed.): 'Physicalism and its Discontents'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Witmer, D. G.

(2003): Dupre's anti-essentialist objection to reductionism. In: 'The Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 53, pp.181-200.
@

Witmer, D. G.; Gillett, C.

(2001): A 'physical' need: Physicalism and the via negativa . In: 'Analysis', vol. 61, pp.302-309.
@

Witmer, G.

(2003): Multiple realizability and psychological laws: Evaluating Kim's challenge . In: S. Walter; H. Heckmann (Ed.): 'Physicalism and Mental Causation'. Imprint Academic.
@

Wittgenstein, L.

(1953): Philosophical Investigations.
@

Wittgenstein, L.

(1977): Remarks on Colour. University of California Press.
@

Wolf, S.

(1980): Asymmetrical freedom. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 77, pp.151-66.
@

Wolf, S.

(1981): The importance of free will. In: 'Mind ', vol. 90, pp.366-78.
@

Wolf, S.

(1986): Self-interest and interest in selves. In: 'Ethics ', vol. 96, pp.704-20.
@

Wolf, S.

(1990): Freedom within Reason. Oxford University Press.
@

Wolfe, J.; Nathan, G. J.

(1968): The identity theory as a scientific hypothesis. In: 'Dialogue', vol. 7, pp.469-72.
@

Wollheim, R.

(1999): On the Emotions. Yale University Press.
@

Wollheim, R.

(2003): Emotions and their philosophy of mind. In: A. Hatimoysis (Ed.): 'Philosophy and the Emotions'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Woodfield, A.

(1982): Thought and the social community. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 25, pp.435-50.
@

Woodfield, A.

(1986): Two categories of content. In: 'Mind and Language ', vol. 1, pp.319-54.
@

Woodfield, A.

(1991): Conceptions. In: 'Mind', vol. 100, pp.547-72.
@

Woodfield, A.

(1998): Social externalism and conceptual diversity. In: J. Preston (Ed.): 'Thought and Language'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Woods, W.

(1981): Procedural semantics as a theory of meaning. In: A. Joshi; B. Weber; I. Sag (Ed.): 'Elements of Discourse Understanding'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Woods, W.

(1986): Problems in procedural semantics. In: Z. Pylyshyn; W. Demopolous (Ed.): 'Meaning and Cognitive Structure'. Ablex.
@

Woody, M. J.

(2003): The unconscious as a hermeneutic myth: A defense of the imagination . In: J. Philips; J. Morley (Ed.): 'Imagination and its Pathologies'. MIT Press.
@

Worley, S.

(1997): Determination and mental causation. In: 'Erkenntnis ', vol. 46, pp.281-304.
@

Wray, K. B.

(2001): Collective belief and acceptance. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 129, pp.319-33.
@

Wright, C.

(1980): Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics. Harvard University Press.
@

Wright, C.

(1981): Rule-following, objectivity and the theory of meaning. In: S. Holtzman; C. Leich (Ed.): 'Wittgenstein: To Follow A Rule'. Routledge.
@

Wright, C.

(1984): Kripke's account of the argument against private language. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 81, pp.759-78.
@

Wright, C.

(1989): Wittgenstein's rule-following considerations and the central project of theoretical linguistics. In: A. George (Ed.): 'Reflections on Chomsky'. Blackwell.
@

Wright, C.

(1991): Wittgenstein's later philosophy of mind: Sensation, privacy and intention . In: K. Puhl (Ed.): 'Meaning Scepticism'. De Gruyter.
@

Wright, C.

(1996): Can there be a rationally compelling argument for anti-realism about ordinary ("folk") psychology?. In: E. Villanueva (Ed.): 'Content'. Ridgeview.
@

Wright, C.

(1998): Wittgenstein and self-knowledge. In: A. O'Hear (Ed.): ' Contemporary Issues in the Philosophy of Mind'. Cambridge University Press.
@

Wright, C.

(2000): Cogency and question-begging: Some reflections on McKinsey's paradox and Putnam's proof. In: ' Philosophical Issues', vol. 10, pp.140-63.
@

Wright, C.

(2000): Self-knowledge: The Wittgensteinian legacy. In: C. Wright; B. Smith; and C. Macdonald; eds. (Ed.): 'Knowing Our Own Minds'. Oxford University Press.
@

Wright, C.

(2001): Rails to Infinity: Essays on Themes from Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations. Harvard University Press.
@

Wright, C.

(2001): The problem of self-knowledge (I & II). In: ' Rails to Infinity'.
@

Wright, C.

(2003): Some reflections on the acquisition of warrant by inference. In: S. Nuccetelli (Ed.): 'New Essays on Semantic Externalism and Self-Knowledge'. MIT Press.
@

Wright, C.; Smith, B.; MacDonald, C.

(2000): Knowing Our Own Minds. Oxford University Press.
@

Wright, E.

(1983): Inspecting images. In: 'Philosophy ', vol. 58, pp.57-72.
@

Wright, J. N.

(1959): Mind and the concept of mind. In: ' Aristotelian Society Supplement', vol. 33, pp.1-22.
@

Wright, R.

(1994): The Moral Animal. Pantheon Books.
@

Wright, W.

(2003): A dilemma for Jackson and Pargetter's account of color. In: 'Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 41, pp.125-42.
@

Wringe, B.

(2003): Simulation, co-cognition, and the attribution of emotional states . In: 'European Journal of Philosophy', vol. 11, pp.353-374.
@

Wyler, T.

(1994): First-person authority and singular thoughts. In: ' Zeitschrift fur Philosophie Forschung', vol. 48, pp.585-94.
@

Wynn, M.

(1999): Emergent phenomena and theistic explanation. In: ' International Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 39, pp.141-55.

X



Y


@

Yablo, S.

(1992): Mental causation. In: 'Philosophical Review ', vol. 101, pp.245-280.
@

Yablo, S.

(1997): Wide causation. In: 'Philosophical Perspectives ', vol. 11, pp.251-81.
@

Yablo, S.

(2001): Superproportionality and mind-body relations. In: 'Theoria ', vol. 16, pp.65-75.
@

Yablo, S.

(2003): Causal relevance. In: 'Philosophical Issues ', vol. 13, pp.316-28.
@

Yaffe, G.

(2000): Free will and agency at its best. In: ' Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.203-230.
@

Yagisawa, T.

(1994): Thinking in neurons: Comments on Stephen Schiffer's "The language-of-thought relation and its implications". In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 76, pp.287-96.
@

Yalowitz, S.

(1997): Rationality and the argument for anomalous monism. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 87, pp.235-58.
@

Yalowitz, S.

(1998): Causation in the argument for anomalous monism. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 28, pp.183-226.
@

Yalowitz, S.

(2002): Individualism, normativity, and the epistemology of understanding . In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 102, pp.43-92.
@

Young, A. W.

(1999): Delusions. In: 'Monist', vol. 82, pp.571-589.
@

Yu, P.; Fuller, G.

(1986): A critique of Dennett. In: 'Synthese ', vol. 66, pp.453-76.
@

Yu, Q.

(1992): Consistency, mechanicalness, and the logic of the mind. In: ' Synthese', vol. 90, pp.145-79.

Z


@

Zagzebski, L.

(2000): Does libertarian freedom require alternate possibilities?. In: 'Philosopical Perspectives', vol. 14, pp.231-248.
@

Zahavi, D.

(2004): The embodied self-awareness of the infant: A challenge to the theory-theory of mind. In: D. Zahavi (Ed.): ' The Structure and Development of Self-Consciousness'. John Benjamins.
@

Zalabardo, J. L.

(1989): Rules, communities and judgement. In: 'Critica ', vol. 21, pp.33-58.
@

Zalabardo, J. L.

(1995): A problem for information-theoretic semantics. In: 'Synthese', vol. 105, pp.1-29.
@

Zalabardo, J. L.

(1997): Kripke's normativity argument. In: ' Canadian Journal of Philosophy', vol. 27, pp.467-488.
@

Zangwill, N.

(1992): Variable realization: not proven. In: ' Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 42, pp.214-19.
@

Zangwill, N.

(1993): Supervenience and anomalous monism: Blackburn on Davidson. In: 'Philosophical Studies', vol. 71, pp.59-79.
@

Zangwill, N.

(1995): Supervenience, reduction, and infinite disjunction. In: 'Philosophia', vol. 24, pp.321-30.
@

Zangwill, N.

(1996): Good old supervenience: Mental causation on the cheap. In: 'Synthese', vol. 106, pp.67-101.
@

Zangwill, N.

(1997): Explaining supervenience: Moral and mental. In: ' Journal of Philosophical Research', vol. 22, pp.509-18.
@

Zawidzki, T.

(2003): Mythological content: A problem for Milikan's teleosemantics. In: 'Philosophical Psychology', vol. 16, pp.535-538.
@

Zawidzki, T.; Ross, D.

(1994): Information and teleosemantics. In: ' Southern Journal of Philosophy', vol. 32, pp.393-419.
@

Zdenek, S.

(2001): Passing Loebner's Turing test: A case of conflicting discourse functions . In: 'Minds & Machines', vol. 11, pp.53-76.
@

Zemach, E.

(1966): Sensations, raw feels, and other minds. In: ' Review of Metaphysics', vol. 20, pp.317-40.
@

Zemach, E.

(1983): Memory: What it is, and what is cannot possibly be. In: ' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research', vol. 44, pp.31-44.
@

Zemach, E.

(1987): Looking out for number one. In: '1987'.
@

Zemach, E. M.

(1976): Putnam's theory on the reference of substance terms. In: 'Journal of Philosophy', vol. 73, pp.116-27.
@

Zhang, J.; Norman, D.

(1994): Representations in distributed cognitive tasks. In: 'Cognitive Science', vol. 18, pp.87-122.
@

Zhu, J.

(2004): Is the conscious will an illusion?. In: 'Disputatio ', vol. 16.
@

Ziedins, R.

(1971): Identification of characteristics of mental events with characteristics of brain events. In: ' American Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 8, pp.13-23.
@

Ziff, P.

(1958): About behaviourism. In: 'Analysis', vol. 18, pp.132-6.
@

Ziff, P.

(1959): The feelings of robots. In: '1959'.
@

Ziff, P.

(1965): The simplicity of other minds. In: 'Journal of Philosophy ', vol. 42, pp.575-84.
@

Zimmerman, A.

(2004): Unnatural access. In: 'Philosophical Quarterly ', vol. 54, pp.435-38.
@

Zimmerman, A.

(2005): Basic self-knowledge: Answering Peacocke's criticisms of constitutivism. In: '2005'.
@

Zimmerman, A.

(2005): Self-verification and the content of thought. In: ' 2005'.
@

Zimmerman, D.

(1981): Hierarchical motivation and the freedom of the will. In: 'Pacific Philosophical Quarterly', vol. 62, pp.354-68.
@

Zimmerman, D.

(1994): Acts, omissions, and semi-compatibilism. In: ' Philosophical Studies', vol. 73, pp.209-23.
@

Zimmerman, D.

(2003): That was then, this is now: Personal history vs. psychological structure in compatibilist theories of autonomy. In: 'Nous', vol. 37, pp.638-671.
@

Zuboff, A.

(1978): Moment universals and personal identity. In: ' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society', vol. 52, pp.141-55.
@

Zuboff, A.

(1990): One self: The logic of experience. In: 'Inquiry ', vol. 33, pp.39-68.